Jump to content

Xenophanes: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
→‎Pantheism: cleanup pantheism section so as not to have to repeat ourselves
Bobconway (talk | contribs)
mNo edit summary
 
(27 intermediate revisions by 16 users not shown)
Line 9: Line 9:
| death_place = [[Syracuse, Sicily]]<br />(modern-day [[Italy]])
| death_place = [[Syracuse, Sicily]]<br />(modern-day [[Italy]])
| main_interests = [[Social criticism]]<br>[[Kataphasis]]<br>[[Natural philosophy]]<br>[[Epistemology]]
| main_interests = [[Social criticism]]<br>[[Kataphasis]]<br>[[Natural philosophy]]<br>[[Epistemology]]
| influences = The [[Milesian School]]
| influenced = [[Epicharmus]], [[Parmenides]], [[Timon of Phlius]], [[Baruch Spinoza]], [[Karl Popper]]
| notable_ideas = Religious polytheistic views as human [[Psychological projection|projections]]<br>Earth and water is the ''[[arche]]'' <br>The distinction between [[knowledge]] and mere [[Justified true belief|true belief]].
| notable_ideas = Religious polytheistic views as human [[Psychological projection|projections]]<br>Earth and water is the ''[[arche]]'' <br>The distinction between [[knowledge]] and mere [[Justified true belief|true belief]].
| image=Xenophanes in Thomas Stanley History of Philosophy.jpg|image_size=190px|caption=Fictionalized portrait of Xenophanes from a 17th-century engraving}}
| image=Xenophanes in Thomas Stanley History of Philosophy.jpg|image_size=190px|caption=Fictionalized portrait of Xenophanes from a 17th-century engraving}}
'''Xenophanes of Colophon''' ({{IPAc-en|z|ə|ˈ|n|ɒ|f|ə|n|iː|z}};<ref>[http://www.collinsdictionary.com/dictionary/english/xenophanes "Xenophanes"] entry in ''[[Collins English Dictionary]]''.</ref><ref>[http://cougar.eb.com/soundc11/bix/bixxen02.wav Sound file]</ref> {{lang-grc|[[wikt:Ξενοφάνης|Ξενοφάνης]] ὁ Κολοφώνιος}} {{IPA-el|ksenopʰánɛːs ho kolopʰɔ̌ːnios|}}; c. 570 – c. 478 BC) was a [[Ancient Greece|Greek]] [[philosopher]], [[theologian]], [[poet]], and [[critic]] of [[Homer]] from [[Ionia]] who travelled throughout the Greek-speaking world in early [[Classical Antiquity]].
'''Xenophanes of Colophon''' ({{IPAc-en|z|ə|ˈ|n|ɒ|f|ə|n|iː|z}} {{respell|zə|NOF|ə|neez}};<ref>[http://www.collinsdictionary.com/dictionary/english/xenophanes "Xenophanes"] entry in ''[[Collins English Dictionary]]''.</ref><ref>[http://cougar.eb.com/soundc11/bix/bixxen02.wav Sound file]</ref> {{lang-grc|[[wikt:Ξενοφάνης|Ξενοφάνης]] ὁ Κολοφώνιος}} {{IPA-el|ksenopʰánɛːs ho kolopʰɔ̌ːnios|}}; c. 570 – c. 478 BC) was a [[Ancient Greece|Greek]] [[philosopher]], [[theologian]], [[poet]], and [[critic]] of [[Homer]] from [[Ionia]] who travelled throughout the Greek-speaking world in early [[Classical Antiquity]].


As a poet, Xenophanes was known for his critical style, writing poems that are considered among the first [[satires]]. He also composed [[elegiac couplets]] that criticised his society's traditional values of wealth, excesses, and athletic victories. He also criticised [[Homer]] and the other poets in his works for representing the gods as foolish or morally weak. His poems have not survived intact; only fragments of some of his work survives in quotations by later philosophers and literary critics.
As a poet, Xenophanes was known for his critical style, writing poems that are considered among the first [[satires]]. He also composed [[elegiac couplets]] that criticised his society's traditional values of wealth, excesses, and athletic victories. He also criticised [[Homer]] and the other poets in his works for representing the gods as foolish or morally weak. His poems have not survived intact; only fragments of some of his work survive in quotations by later philosophers and literary critics.


Xenophanes is seen as one of the most important [[Pre-Socratic philosophy|pre-Socratic philosophers]]. A highly original thinker, Xenophanes sought explanations for physical phenomena such as clouds or rainbows without references to divine or mythological explanations, but instead based on [[arche|first principles]]. He also distinguished between different forms of knowledge and belief as an early proponent of [[epistemology]]. Later philosophers such as the [[Eleatics]] and the [[Pyrrhonists]] also saw Xenophanes as the founder of their doctrines, and interpreted his work in terms of those doctrines, although modern scholarship disputes these claims.
Xenophanes is seen as one of the most important [[Pre-Socratic philosophy|pre-Socratic philosophers]]. A highly original thinker, Xenophanes sought explanations for physical phenomena such as clouds or rainbows without references to divine or mythological explanations, but instead based on [[arche|first principles]]. He also distinguished between different forms of knowledge and belief, an early instance of [[epistemology]]. Later philosophers such as the [[Eleatics]] and the [[Pyrrhonists]] also saw Xenophanes as the founder of their doctrines, and interpreted his work in terms of those doctrines, although modern scholarship disputes these claims.


{{toclimit|3}}
{{toclimit|3}}


==Life==
==Life==
The Ancient biographer [[Diogenes Laertius]] reports that Xenophanes was born in [[Colophon (city)|Colophon]], a city that once existed in Ionia, in present day Turkey.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}}{{efn|{{harv|DK 21A1}}}} Laertius says that Xenophanes is said to have flourished during the 60th [[Olympiad]] (540–537 BC),{{efn|Diogenes Laertius, ix. 18-20 {{harv|DK 21A1}}}} and modern scholars generally place his birth some time around 570-560 BC.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}} His surviving work refers to [[Thales]], [[Epimenides]], and [[Pythagoras]],{{efn|Diogenes Laertius}} and he himself is mentioned in the writings of [[Heraclitus]] and [[Epicharmus]].{{efn|Diogenes Laertius, ix. 1; Aristotle, ''Metaphysics''}}
The Ancient biographer [[Diogenes Laertius]] reports that Xenophanes was born in [[Colophon (city)|Colophon]], a city that once existed in Ionia, in present-day Turkey.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}}{{efn|{{harv|DK 21A1}}}} Laertius says that Xenophanes is said to have flourished during the 60th [[Olympiad]] (540–537 BC),{{efn|Diogenes Laertius, ix. 18-20 {{harv|DK 21A1}}}} and modern scholars generally place his birth some time around 570-560 BC.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}} His surviving work refers to [[Thales]], [[Epimenides]], and [[Pythagoras]],{{efn|Diogenes Laertius}} and he himself is mentioned in the writings of [[Heraclitus]] and [[Epicharmus]].{{efn|Diogenes Laertius, ix. 1; Aristotle, ''Metaphysics''}}


By his own surviving account,{{efn|{{harv|DK 21B8}}}} he was an itinerant poet who left his native land at the age of 25 and then lived 67 years in other Greek lands, dying at or after the age of 92.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}} Although ancient testimony notes that he buried his sons, there is little other biographical information about him or his family that can be reliably ascertained.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}}
By his own surviving account,{{efn|{{harv|DK 21B8}}}} he was an itinerant poet who left his native land at the age of 25 and then lived 67 years in other Greek lands, dying at or after the age of 92.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}} Although ancient testimony notes that he buried his sons, there is little other biographical information about him or his family that can be reliably ascertained.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}}


It is considered likely Xenophanes' physical theories were influenced by the [[Milesian school|Milesians]]. For instance, his theory that the rainbow is clouds is on one interpretation seen as a response to [[Anaximenes of Miletus|Anaximenes's]] theory that the rainbow is light reflected off of clouds.<ref>{{cite book|url=https://www.google.com/books/edition/Xenophanes_of_Colophon/LxxJXTviacgC|page=140|title=Fragments|author=Xenophanes|editor=James H. Lesher}}</ref>
It is considered likely Xenophanes' physical theories were influenced by the [[Milesian school|Milesians]]. For instance, his theory that the rainbow is clouds is on one interpretation seen as a response to [[Anaximenes of Miletus|Anaximenes's]] theory that the rainbow is light reflected off of clouds.<ref>{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LxxJXTviacgC|page=140|title=Fragments|author=Xenophanes|date=January 2001 |publisher=University of Toronto Press |isbn=9780802085085 |editor=James H. Lesher}}</ref>


==Poems==
==Poems==
[[File:Map_of_the_Presocratic_Greek_World.png|thumb|280px|Xenophanes characterised his travels as "tossing up and down{{efn|{{harv|DK 21B8}}}}" [[Ancient Greece]] in the [[Archaic Greece|archaic period]]. His travels took him from [[Colophon (city)|Colophon]], [[Ionia]] in present day [[Turkey]] as far as [[Greek colonization|colonies]] in [[Magna Graecia]] in present day [[Italy]]{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}}]]
[[File:Map_of_the_Presocratic_Greek_World.png|thumb|upright=1.35|Xenophanes characterised his travels as "tossing up and down{{efn|{{harv|DK 21B8}}}}" [[Ancient Greece]] in the [[Archaic Greece|archaic period]]. His travels took him from [[Colophon (city)|Colophon]], [[Ionia]] in present-day [[Turkey]] as far as [[Greek colonization|colonies]] in [[Magna Graecia]] in present-day [[Italy]]{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}}]]
Knowledge of Xenophanes' views comes from fragments of his poetry that survive as quotations by later Greek writers. Unlike other pre-socratic philosophers such as [[Heraclitus]] or [[Parmenides]], who only wrote one work, Xenophanes wrote a variety of poems, and no two of the fragments can positively be identified as belonging to the same text.{{sfn|Mackenzie|2021|p=24-27}} According to Diogenes Laertius{{efn|DK 28A1}}, Xenophanes wrote a poem on the foundation of Colophon and Elea, which ran to approximately 2000 lines.{{sfn|Mackenzie|2021|p=24-27}} Later testimony also suggests that his collection of satires was assembled in at least five books.{{sfn|DK 21B21a}} Although many later sources attribute a poem titled "On Nature" to Xenophanes, modern scholars doubt this label, as it was likely a name given by scholars at the [[Library of Alexandria]] to works written by philosophers that Aristotle had identified as "[[wikt:φυσικοί|phusikoi]]" who studied nature.{{sfn|Mackenzie|2021|p=24-27}}
Knowledge of Xenophanes' views comes from fragments of his poetry that survive as quotations by later Greek writers. Unlike other pre-socratic philosophers such as [[Heraclitus]] or [[Parmenides]], who only wrote one work, Xenophanes wrote a variety of poems, and no two of the fragments can positively be identified as belonging to the same text.{{sfn|Mackenzie|2021|p=24-27}} According to Diogenes Laertius,{{efn|DK 28A1}} Xenophanes wrote a poem on the foundation of Colophon and Elea, which ran to approximately 2000 lines.{{sfn|Mackenzie|2021|p=24-27}} Later testimony also suggests that his collection of satires was assembled in at least five books.{{sfn|DK 21B21a}} Although many later sources attribute a poem titled "On Nature" to Xenophanes, modern scholars doubt this label, as it was likely a name given by scholars at the [[Library of Alexandria]] to works written by philosophers that Aristotle had identified as "[[wikt:φυσικοί|phusikoi]]" who studied nature.{{sfn|Mackenzie|2021|p=24-27}}


=== Satires ===
=== Satires ===
Line 37: Line 35:
Xenophanes' surviving writings display a skepticism that became more commonly expressed during the fourth century BC. Several of the philosophical fragments are derived from commentators on Homer. He aimed his critique at the polytheistic religious views of earlier Greek poets and of his own contemporaries
Xenophanes' surviving writings display a skepticism that became more commonly expressed during the fourth century BC. Several of the philosophical fragments are derived from commentators on Homer. He aimed his critique at the polytheistic religious views of earlier Greek poets and of his own contemporaries


To judge from these later accounts{{efn|Diogenes Laertius, ix. 18-20 {{harv|DK 21A1}}}}, his [[elegiac]] and [[Iamb (foot)|iambic]] poetry criticized and [[satire|satirized]] a wide range of ideas, including [[Homer]] and [[Hesiod]],{{sfn|Barnes|1982|p=40}} the belief in the [[pantheon (gods)|pantheon]] of [[anthropomorphic]] [[deity|gods]] and the Greeks' veneration of [[wikt:athleticism|athleticism]].
To judge from these later accounts,{{efn|Diogenes Laertius, ix. 18-20 {{harv|DK 21A1}}}} his [[elegiac]] and [[Iamb (foot)|iambic]] poetry criticized and [[satire|satirized]] a wide range of ideas, including [[Homer]] and [[Hesiod]],{{sfn|Barnes|1982|p=40}} the belief in the [[pantheon (gods)|pantheon]] of [[anthropomorphic]] [[deity|gods]] and the Greeks' veneration of [[wikt:athleticism|athleticism]].


=== On Nature ===
=== On Nature ===
There is no good authority that says that Xenophanes specifically wrote a philosophical poem.{{sfn|Burnet|1892}} John Burnet says that "The oldest reference to a poem Περὶ φύσεως is in the Geneva scholium on ''Iliad'' xxi. 196{{efn|DK 21B30}}, and this goes back to [[Crates of Mallus]]. We must remember that such titles are of later date, and Xenophanes had been given a place among philosophers long before the time of rates. All we can say, therefore, is that the Pergamene librarians gave the title Περὶ φύσεως to some poem of Xenophanes." However, even if Xenophanes never wrote a specific poem title ''On Nature'', many of the suriviving fragments deal with topics in natural philosophy such as clouds or rainbows, and it is thus likely that the philosophical remarks of Xenophanes were expressed incidentally in his satires.{{sfn|Burnet|1892}}
There is no good authority that says that Xenophanes specifically wrote a philosophical poem.{{sfn|Burnet|1892}} John Burnet says that "The oldest reference to a poem Περὶ φύσεως is in the Geneva scholium on ''Iliad'' xxi. 196,{{efn|DK 21B30}} and this goes back to [[Crates of Mallus]]. We must remember that such titles are of later date, and Xenophanes had been given a place among philosophers long before the time of Crates. All we can say, therefore, is that the Pergamene librarians gave the title Περὶ φύσεως to some poem of Xenophanes." However, even if Xenophanes never wrote a specific poem title ''On Nature'', many of the surviving fragments deal with topics in natural philosophy such as clouds or rainbows, and it is thus likely that the philosophical remarks of Xenophanes were expressed incidentally in his satires.{{sfn|Burnet|1892}}


==Philosophy==
==Philosophy==
Although Xenophanes has traditionally been interpreted in terms of the [[Eleatics]] and [[Skeptics]] who were influenced by him and saw him as their predecessor and founder, modern scholarship has revealed him to be a highly original and distinct philosopher whose philosophy extends well beyond the influence he had on later philosophical schools.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}} As a social critic, Xenophanes composed poems on proper behavior at a [[symposium]] and criticized the cultural glorification of athletes.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}} Xenophanes sought to reform the understanding of [[divinity|divine nature]] by casting doubt on Greek mythology as relayed by [[Hesiod]] and [[Homer]], in order to make it more consistent with notions of piety from [[Ancient Greek religion]].{{sfn|Lesher|2019}} He composed natural explanations for phenomena such as the formation of [[clouds]] and [[rainbows]] rather than myths,{{sfn|Lesher|2019}} satirizing traditional religious views of his time as human [[Psychological projection|projections]].{{sfn|Johansen|1999|p=49}} As an early thinker in [[epistemology]], he drew distinctions between the ideas of knowledge and belief as opposed to [[truth]], which he believed was only possible for the gods.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}}
Although Xenophanes has traditionally been interpreted in terms of the [[Eleatics]] and [[Skeptics]] who were influenced by him and saw him as their predecessor and founder, modern scholarship has revealed him to be a highly original and distinct philosopher whose philosophy extends well beyond the influence he had on later philosophical schools.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}} As a social critic, Xenophanes composed poems on proper behavior at a [[symposium]] and criticized the cultural glorification of athletes.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}} Xenophanes sought to reform the understanding of [[divinity|divine nature]] by casting doubt on Greek mythology as relayed by [[Hesiod]] and [[Homer]], in order to make it more consistent with notions of piety from [[Ancient Greek religion]].{{sfn|Lesher|2019}} He composed natural explanations for phenomena such as the formation of [[clouds]] and [[rainbows]] rather than myths,{{sfn|Lesher|2019}} satirizing traditional religious views of his time as human [[Psychological projection|projections]].{{sfn|Johansen|1999|p=49}} As an early thinker in [[epistemology]], he drew distinctions between the ideas of knowledge and belief as opposed to [[truth]], which he believed was only possible for the gods.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}}


[[File:Black figure epinetron, symposion scene, AM of Corinth, 202835x.jpg|thumb|left|220px| 6th century BC depiction of an Ancient Greek [[symposium]]. Xenophanes criticized these drinking parties as they were celebrated in his time for their excesses and failures to honor the gods.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}}]]
=== Social criticism ===
=== Social criticism ===
[[File:Black figure epinetron, symposion scene, AM of Corinth, 202835x.jpg|thumb|upright=1.15|6th century BC depiction of an Ancient Greek [[symposium]]. Xenophanes criticized these drinking parties as they were celebrated in his time for their excesses and failures to honor the gods.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}}]]
Xenophanes wrote a number of elegiac poems on proper conduct at a [[symposium]],{{sfn|Lesher|2019}} the Ancient Greek drinking parties that were held in commemorate athletic or poetic victories, or to welcome young men into aristocratic society. The surviving fragments stress the importance of piety and honor to the gods{{efn|To hymn the praises of the Gods; and so / With pure libations and well-order'd vows / To win from them the power to act with justice / For this comes from the favour of the Gods;{{harv|DK 21B1}}}}, and they discourage drunkenness{{efn|And never let a man a goblet take / And first pour in the wine; but let the water / Come first, and after that, then add the wine.{{harv|DK 21B5}}}} and intemperance, endorsing moderation and criticism of luxury and excess{{efn|They learnt all sorts of useless foolishness / From the effeminate Lydians, while they / Were held in bondage to sharp tyranny / They went into the forum richly clad / In purple garments, in numerous companies / Whose strength was not less than a thousand men / Boasting of hair luxuriously dress'd / Dripping with costly and sweet-smelling oils.{{harv|DK 21B3}}}}. Xenophanes also rejected the value of athletic victories, stating that cultivating wisdom was more important.{{efn|For wisdom far exceeds in real value / The bodily strength of man, or horses' speed;/ But the mob judges of such things at random; / Though 'tis not right to prefer strength to sense:{{harv|DK 21B2}}}}.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}}
Xenophanes wrote a number of elegiac poems on proper conduct at a [[symposium]],{{sfn|Lesher|2019}} the Ancient Greek drinking parties that were held to commemorate athletic or poetic victories, or to welcome young men into aristocratic society. The surviving fragments stress the importance of piety and honor to the gods,{{efn|To hymn the praises of the Gods; and so / With pure libations and well-order'd vows / To win from them the power to act with justice / For this comes from the favour of the Gods;{{harv|DK 21B1}}}} and they discourage drunkenness{{efn|And never let a man a goblet take / And first pour in the wine; but let the water / Come first, and after that, then add the wine.{{harv|DK 21B5}}}} and intemperance, endorsing moderation and criticism of luxury and excess.{{efn|They learnt all sorts of useless foolishness / From the effeminate Lydians, while they / Were held in bondage to sharp tyranny / They went into the forum richly clad / In purple garments, in numerous companies / Whose strength was not less than a thousand men / Boasting of hair luxuriously dress'd / Dripping with costly and sweet-smelling oils.{{harv|DK 21B3}}}} Xenophanes also rejected the value of athletic victories, stating that cultivating wisdom was more important.{{efn|For wisdom far exceeds in real value / The bodily strength of man, or horses' speed;/ But the mob judges of such things at random; / Though 'tis not right to prefer strength to sense:{{harv|DK 21B2}}}}{{sfn|Lesher|2019}}


=== Divine Nature ===
=== Divine Nature ===
[[Orphism (religion)|Orphism]] and [[Pythagoreanism|Pythagorean philosophy]] introduced into the Greek spirituality the notions of guilt and pureness, causing a dichotomic belief between the divine soul and the mortal body. This doctrine is in contrast with the traditional religions as espoused by [[Homer]] and [[Hesiod]].{{sfn|Meza|2010|p=55-57}} God moves all things, but he is thought to be immobile, characterized by oneness{{efn|"One god, the greatest among gods and men, neither in form like unto mortals nor in thought." {{harv|DK 21B23}}}}{{sfn|Burnet|1892|p=119}} and unicity, eternity,{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B26}}}} and a spiritual nature which is bodiless and isn't anthropomorphic.{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B14-15}}, {{harvnb|DK 21B16}}}} He has a free will and is the Highest Good, he embodies the beauty of the moral perfection and of the absence of sin.{{sfn|Meza|2010|p=55-57}}
[[Orphism (religion)|Orphism]] and [[Pythagoreanism|Pythagorean philosophy]] introduced into the Greek spirituality the notions of guilt and pureness, causing a dichotomic belief between the divine soul and the mortal body. This doctrine is in contrast with the traditional religions as espoused by [[Homer]] and [[Hesiod]].{{sfn|Meza|2010|p=55-57}} God moves all things, but he is thought to be immobile, characterized by oneness{{efn|"One god, the greatest among gods and men, neither in form like unto mortals nor in thought." {{harv|DK 21B23}}}}{{sfn|Burnet|1892|p=119}} and unicity, eternity,{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B26}}}} and a spiritual nature which is bodiless and isn't anthropomorphic.{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B14-15}}, {{harvnb|DK 21B16}}}} He has a free will and is the Highest Good, he embodies the beauty of the moral perfection and of the absence of sin.{{sfn|Meza|2010|p=55-57}}


Xenophanes espoused a belief that "[[God]] is one, supreme among gods and men, and not like mortals in body or in mind." He maintained there was one greatest God. God is one eternal being, spherical in form, comprehending all things within himself, is the absolute [[Nous|mind]] and thought,{{efn|Diogenes Laertius, ix. 18-20 {{harv|DK 21A1}}}} therefore is intelligent, and moves all things, but bears no resemblance to human nature either in body or mind. While Xenophanes is rejecting Homeric theology, he is not questioning the presence of a divine entity, rather his philosophy is a critique on Ancient Greek writers and their conception of divinity.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=60-62}} Regarding Xenophanes' [[kataphasis|positive theology]] five key concepts about God can be formed. God is: beyond human morality, does not resemble human form, cannot die or be born (God is divine thus eternal), no divine hierarchy exists, and God does not intervene in human affairs.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=60-62}}
Xenophanes espoused a belief that "[[God]] is one, supreme among gods and men, and not like mortals in body or in mind." He maintained that there was one greatest God. God is one eternal being, spherical in form, comprehending all things within himself, is the absolute [[Nous|mind]] and thought,{{efn|Diogenes Laertius, ix. 18-20 {{harv|DK 21A1}}}} therefore is intelligent, and moves all things, but bears no resemblance to human nature either in body or mind. While Xenophanes rejected Homeric theology, he did not question the presence of a divine entity; rather his philosophy was a critique on Ancient Greek writers and their conception of divinity.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=60-62}} Regarding Xenophanes' [[kataphasis|positive theology]] five key concepts about God can be formed. God is: beyond human morality, does not resemble human form, cannot die or be born (God is divine thus eternal), no divine hierarchy exists, and God does not intervene in human affairs.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=60-62}}


=== Natural Philosophy ===
=== Natural Philosophy ===
[[File:Elmo's fire.jpg|thumb| Xenophanes was likely the first philosopher to offer a naturalistic rather than a mythological explanation for [[St. Elmo's Fire]].{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=134}}]]
[[File:Elmo's fire.jpg|thumb| Xenophanes was likely the first philosopher to offer a naturalistic rather than a mythological explanation for [[St. Elmo's Fire]].{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=134}}]]
Xenophanes' understanding of divine nature as separate and uninvolved in human affairs motivated him to come up with naturalistic explanations for physical phenomena.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}}
Xenophanes' understanding of divine nature as separate and uninvolved in human affairs motivated him to come up with naturalistic explanations for physical phenomena.{{sfn|Lesher|2019}}


Xenophanes was likely the first philosopher to come up with an explanation for the manifestation of [[St. Elmo's fire]] that appears on the masts of ships when they pass through clouds during a thunderstorm. Although the actual phenomenon behind St. Elmo's fire would not be understood until the discovery of static electricity in the modern era, Xenophanes' explanation, which attempted to explain the glow as being caused by agitations of small droplets of clouds{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A39}}:"Those star-like apparitions mariners call the [[Dioskouroi]]—they are in reality clouds: small ones that glow because of some agitation."}} was unique in the ancient world.{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=134}}
Xenophanes was likely the first philosopher to come up with an explanation for the manifestation of [[St. Elmo's fire]] that appears on the masts of ships when they pass through clouds during a thunderstorm. Although the actual phenomenon behind St. Elmo's fire would not be understood until the discovery of static electricity in the modern era, Xenophanes' explanation, which attempted to explain the glow as being caused by agitations of small droplets of clouds{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A39}}:"Those star-like apparitions mariners call the [[Dioskouroi]]—they are in reality clouds: small ones that glow because of some agitation."}} was unique in the ancient world.{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=134}}


In Xenophanes' cosmology, there is only one boundary to the universe,{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=138-139}} the one "seen by our feet"{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A28}}}}. Xenophanes believed that the earth extended infinitely far down, as well as infinitely far in every direction.{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=138-139}} A consequence of his belief in an infinitely extended earth was that rather than having the sun pass under the earth at sunset, Xenophanes believed that the sun and the moon traveled along a straight line westward,{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21 A41a}}}} after which point a new sun or moon would be reconstituted after an eclipse.{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21 A41a}}}}{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=138-139}} While this potentially infinite series of suns and moons traveling would likely be considered objectionable to modern scientists,{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=138-139}} this means that Xenophanes understood the sun and moon as a "type" of object that appeared in the sky, rather than a specific individual object that reappeared every new day.{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=138-139}}
In Xenophanes' cosmology, there is only one boundary to the universe,{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=138-139}} the one "seen by our feet".{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A28}}}} Xenophanes believed that the earth extended infinitely far down, as well as infinitely far in every direction.{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=138-139}} A consequence of his belief in an infinitely extended earth was that rather than having the sun pass under the earth at sunset, Xenophanes believed that the sun and the moon traveled along a straight line westward,{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21 A41a}}}} after which point a new sun or moon would be reconstituted after an eclipse.{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21 A41a}}}}{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=138-139}} While this potentially infinite series of suns and moons traveling would likely be considered objectionable to modern scientists,{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=138-139}} this means that Xenophanes understood the sun and moon as a "type" of object that appeared in the sky, rather than a specific individual object that reappeared every new day.{{sfn|Mourelatos|2008|p=138-139}}


Xenophanes concluded from his examination of [[fossil]]s of sea creatures that were found above land{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A33}}}} that [[water]] once must have covered all of the [[Earth]]'s surface.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=66}} He used this evidence to conclude that the ''[[arche]]'' or cosmic principle of the universe was a tide flowing in and out between wet and dry, or earth (γῆ) and water (ὕδωρ). These two extreme states would alternate between one another, and with the alternation human life would become extinct, then regenerate (or vice versa depending on the dominant form).{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=65-66}} The argument can be considered a rebuke to [[Anaximenes of Miletus|Anaximenes]]' air theory.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=65-66}} The idea of alternating states and human life perishing and coming back suggests he believed in the principle of causation, another distinguishing step that Xenophanes takes away from Ancient philosophical traditions to ones based more on scientific observation.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=66}}{{clarify|date=April 2023}} This use of [[evidence]] was an important step in advancing from simply stating an idea to backing it up by evidence and observation.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=65-66}}
Xenophanes concluded from his examination of [[fossil]]s of sea creatures that were found above land{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A33}}}} that [[water]] once must have covered all of the [[Earth]]'s surface.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=66}} He used this evidence to conclude that the ''[[arche]]'' or cosmic principle of the universe was a tide flowing in and out between wet and dry, or earth (γῆ) and water (ὕδωρ). These two extreme states would alternate between one another, and with the alternation human life would become extinct, then regenerate (or vice versa depending on the dominant form).{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=65-66}} The argument can be considered a rebuke to [[Anaximenes of Miletus|Anaximenes]]' air theory.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=65-66}} The idea of alternating states and human life perishing and coming back suggests he believed in the principle of causation, another distinguishing step that Xenophanes takes away from Ancient philosophical traditions to ones based more on scientific observation.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=66}}{{clarify|date=April 2023}} This use of [[evidence]] was an important step in advancing from simply stating an idea to backing it up by evidence and observation.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=65-66}}


=== Epistemology ===
=== Epistemology ===
Xenophanes is one of the first philosophers to show interest in [[Epistemology|epistemological]] questions as well as metaphysical ones. He held that there actually exists an objective [[truth]] in [[reality]],{{efn|{{harv|DK 21B18}}}} but that as mere mortals, humans are [[acatalepsy|unable to know it]].{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B34}}}} He is also credited with being one of the first philosophers to distinguish between [[justified true belief|true belief]] and [[knowledge]],{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B34}}}} as well as acknowledge the prospect that one can think he knows something but not really know it.{{sfn|Osborne|2004|p=66-67}}
Xenophanes is one of the first philosophers to show interest in [[Epistemology|epistemological]] questions as well as metaphysical ones. He held that there actually exists an objective [[truth]] in [[reality]],{{efn|{{harv|DK 21B18}}}} but that as mere mortals, humans are [[acatalepsy|unable to know it]].{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B34}}}} He is also credited with being one of the first philosophers to distinguish between [[justified true belief|true belief]] and [[knowledge]],{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B34}}}} as well as acknowledge the prospect that one can think he knows something but not really know it.{{sfn|Osborne|2004|p=66-67}}


His verses on skepticism are quoted by [[Sextus Empiricus]] as follows:
His verses on skepticism are quoted by [[Sextus Empiricus]] as follows:
<poem>
<poem>
Yet, with respect to the gods and what I declare about all things.
Yet, with regard to the gods and what I declare about all things:
No man has seen what is clear nor ever will any man know it.
No man has seen what is clear nor will any man ever know it.
Nay, for e’en should he chance to affirm what is really existent,
Nay, for even should he chance to affirm what is really existent,
He himself knoweth it not ; for all is swayed by opining.{{efn|quoted by [[Sextus Empiricus]],{{harv|DK 21B34}}}}</poem>
He himself knoweth it not; for all is swayed by opining.{{efn|quoted by [[Sextus Empiricus]],{{harv|DK 21B34}}}}</poem>
Due to the lack of whole works by Xenophanes, his views are difficult to interpret, so that the implication of knowing being something deeper ("a clearer truth") may have special implications, or it may mean that you cannot know something just by looking at it.{{sfn|Osborne|2004|p=66-67}} It is known that the most and widest variety of evidence was considered by Xenophanes to be the surest way to prove a theory.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=66}}
Due to the lack of whole works by Xenophanes, his views are difficult to interpret, so that the implication of knowing being something deeper ("a clearer truth") may have special implications, or it may mean that you cannot know something just by looking at it.{{sfn|Osborne|2004|p=66-67}} It is known that the most and widest variety of evidence was considered by Xenophanes to be the surest way to prove a theory.{{sfn|McKirahan|1994|p=66}}


Line 79: Line 77:


=== Influence on Eleatics ===
=== Influence on Eleatics ===
Many later ancient accounts associate Xenophanes with the Greek colony in the Italian city of [[Velia|Elea]], either as the author of a poem on the founding of that city,{{efn|DK 28A1}} or as the founder of the [[Eleatic]] school of philosophy,{{efn|A8,30,36}} or as the teacher of [[Parmenides of Elea]].{{efn|A2,A30,A31}} Others associate him with [[Pythagoreanism]]. However, modern scholars generally believe that there is little historical or philosophical justification for these associations between Pythagoras, Xenophanes, and Parmenides as is oft alleged in succession of the so-called "[[Italian School (philosophy)|Italian School]]".{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}} It had similarly been common since [[Ancient history|antiquity]] to see Xenophanes as the teacher of [[Zeno of Elea]], the colleague of Parmenides, but common opinion today is likewise that this is false.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=102}}
Many later ancient accounts associate Xenophanes with the Greek colony in the Italian city of [[Velia|Elea]], either as the author of a poem on the founding of that city,{{efn|DK 28A1}} or as the founder of the [[Eleatic]] school of philosophy,{{efn|A8,30,36}} or as the teacher of [[Parmenides of Elea]].{{efn|A2, A30, A31}} Others associate him with [[Pythagoreanism]]. However, modern scholars generally believe that there is little historical or philosophical justification for these associations between Pythagoras, Xenophanes, and Parmenides as is oft alleged in succession of the so-called "[[Italian school (philosophy)|Italian school]]".{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=3-4}} It had similarly been common since [[Ancient history|antiquity]] to see Xenophanes as the teacher of [[Zeno of Elea]], the colleague of Parmenides, but common opinion today is likewise that this is false.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p=102}}


{{Quote | In his ninety-second year he was still, we have seen, leading a wandering life, which is hardly consistent with the statement that he settled at Elea and founded a school there, especially if we are to think of him as spending his last days at [[Hiero I of Syracuse|Hieron]]'s court. It is very remarkable that no ancient writer expressly says he ever was at Elea, and all the evidence we have seems inconsistent with his having settled there at all.{{sfn|Burnet|1892|p=115}}}}It had been common since [[Ancient history|antiquity]] to see Xenophanes as the teacher of [[Zeno of Elea]], the colleague of [[Parmenides]], and generally associated with the [[Eleatic school]], but common opinion today is likewise that this is false.{{sfn|Lesher|1992|p= 102}}
{{Blockquote | In his ninety-second year he was still, we have seen, leading a wandering life, which is hardly consistent with the statement that he settled at Elea and founded a school there, especially if we are to think of him as spending his last days at [[Hiero I of Syracuse|Hieron]]'s court. It is very remarkable that no ancient writer expressly says he ever was at Elea, and all the evidence we have seems inconsistent with his having settled there at all.{{sfn|Burnet|1892|p=115}}}}


=== Influence on Pyrrhonism ===
=== Influence on Pyrrhonism ===
Xenophanes is sometimes considered the first [[Philosophical skepticism|skeptic]] in Western philosophy.<ref>Xenophanes' Scepticism by James H. Lesher, ''Phronesis'' Vol. 23, No. 1 (1978), pp. 1-21 </ref>{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B49}}}} Xenophanes's alleged skepticism can also be seen as a precursor to [[Pyrrhonism]]. Sextus quotes Pyrrho's follower Timon as praising Xenophanes and dedicating his satires to him, and giving him as an example of somebody who is not a perfect skeptic (like Pyrrho), but who is forgivably close to it.<ref>{{cite book|url=https://www.google.com/books/edition/From_Epicurus_to_Epictetus/|page=86|title=From Epicurus to Epictetus|author=A. A. Long}}</ref>
Xenophanes is sometimes considered the first [[Philosophical skepticism|skeptic]] in Western philosophy.<ref>Xenophanes' Scepticism by James H. Lesher, ''Phronesis'' Vol. 23, No. 1 (1978), pp. 1-21</ref>{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B49}}}} Xenophanes's alleged skepticism can also be seen as a precursor to [[Pyrrhonism]]. Sextus quotes Pyrrho's follower Timon as praising Xenophanes and dedicating his satires to him, and giving him as an example of somebody who is not a perfect skeptic (like Pyrrho), but who is forgivably close to it.<ref>{{cite book|page=86|title=From Epicurus to Epictetus|author=A. A. Long}}</ref>


[[Eusebius]] quoting [[Aristocles of Messene]] says that Xenophanes was the founder of a line of philosophy that culminated in Pyrrhonism. This line begins with Xenophanes and goes through [[Parmenides]], [[Melissus of Samos]], [[Zeno of Elea]], [[Leucippus]], [[Democritus]], [[Protagoras]], [[Nessos of Chios]], [[Metrodorus of Chios]], Diogenes of Smyrna, [[Anaxarchus]], and finally [[Pyrrho]].{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A49}}}}
[[Eusebius]] quoting [[Aristocles of Messene]] says that Xenophanes was the founder of a line of philosophy that culminated in Pyrrhonism. This line begins with Xenophanes and goes through [[Parmenides]], [[Melissus of Samos]], [[Zeno of Elea]], [[Leucippus]], [[Democritus]], [[Protagoras]], [[Nessos of Chios]], [[Metrodorus of Chios]], Diogenes of Smyrna, [[Anaxarchus]], and finally [[Pyrrho]].{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A49}}}}


=== Pantheism ===
=== Pantheism ===
Because of his development of the concept of a "one [[god]] greatest among gods and men," Xenophanes is often seen as one of the first [[Monotheism|monotheists]] in [[Western world|Western]] [[philosophy of religion]]. However, the same referenced quotation refers to multiple "gods" who the supreme God is greater than.<ref>{{Citation |last=Lesher |first=James |title=Xenophanes |date=2021 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/xenophanes/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |access-date=2022-06-12 |edition=Summer 2021 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University}}</ref> This god "shakes all things" by the power of his thought alone. Differently from the human creatures, God has the power to give "immediate execution" (in Greek: ''to phren'') and make effective his cognitive faculty (in Greek: ''nous'').{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B25}}}}
Because of his development of the concept of a "one [[god]] greatest among gods and men," Xenophanes is often seen as one of the first [[Monotheism|monotheists]] in [[Western world|Western]] [[philosophy of religion]]. However, the same referenced quotation refers to multiple "gods" who the supreme God is greater than.{{sfn|Lesher|2021}} This god "shakes all things" by the power of his thought alone. Differently from the human creatures, God has the power to give "immediate execution" (in Greek: ''to phren'') and make effective his cognitive faculty (in Greek: ''nous'').{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21B25}}}}


The thought of Xenophanes was summarized as [[monolatry|monolatrous]] and [[pantheism|pantheistic]] by the ancient [[doxography|doxographies]] of [[Aristotle]], [[Cicero]], [[Diogenes Laertius]], [[Sextus Empiricus]], and [[Plutarch]]. More particularly, Aristotle's [[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|''Metaphysics'']] summarized his view as "the All is God" {{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A30}}}}. The pseudo-Aristotlelian treatise ''[[On Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias]]'' also contains a significant testimony of his teachings {{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A28}}}}. [[Pierre Bayle]] considered Xenophanes views similar to [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]].<ref>Bayle, Critical Dictionary, p. 574</ref> Physicist and philosopher [[Max Bernhard Weinstein]] specifically identified Xenophanes as one of the earliest [[pandeist]]s.{{efn|"Pandeistisch ist, wenn der Eleate Xenophanes (aus Kolophon um 580-492 v. Chr.) von Gott gesagt haben soll: "Er ist ganz und gar Geist und Gedanke und ewig", "er sieht ganz und gar, er denkt ganz und gar, er hört ganz und gar."{{sfn|Weinstein|1910|p=231}}}}
The thought of Xenophanes was summarized as [[monolatry|monolatrous]] and [[pantheism|pantheistic]] by the ancient [[doxography|doxographies]] of [[Aristotle]], [[Cicero]], [[Diogenes Laertius]], [[Sextus Empiricus]], and [[Plutarch]]. More particularly, Aristotle's [[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|''Metaphysics'']] summarized his view as "the All is God."{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A30}}}} The pseudo-Aristotlelian treatise ''[[On Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias]]'' also contains a significant testimony of his teachings.{{efn|{{harvnb|DK 21A28}}}} [[Pierre Bayle]] considered Xenophanes views similar to [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]].<ref>Bayle, Critical Dictionary, p. 574</ref> Physicist and philosopher [[Max Bernhard Weinstein]] specifically identified Xenophanes as one of the earliest [[pandeist]]s.{{efn|"Pandeistisch ist, wenn der Eleate Xenophanes (aus Kolophon um 580-492 v. Chr.) von Gott gesagt haben soll: "Er ist ganz und gar Geist und Gedanke und ewig", "er sieht ganz und gar, er denkt ganz und gar, er hört ganz und gar."{{sfn|Weinstein|1910|p=231}}}}


Xenophanes's view of an impersonal god seemed to influence the pre-socratic Empedocles, who viewed god as an impersonal mind.<ref>"Empedocles" Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1961) by Charles Kahn, p. 498</ref> However, Empedocles called Xenophanes view that Earth extends downward forever to be foolishness.<ref>DK31B39</ref>
Xenophanes's view of an impersonal god seemed to influence the pre-socratic Empedocles, who viewed god as an incorporeal mind.<ref>"Empedocles" Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1961) by Charles Kahn, p. 498</ref> However, Empedocles called Xenophanes's view that [[flat earth|Earth is flat]] and extends [[turtles all the way down|downward forever]] to be foolishness.<ref>DK 21B28</ref><ref>DK31B39</ref>


== Notes ==
== Notes ==
Line 108: Line 106:
The most recent edition of this catalogue is {{cite book |last1=Diels |first1=Hermann |last2=Kranz |first2=Walther |editor-last1=Plamböck |editor-first1=Gert |title=Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker |date=1957 |publisher=Rowohlt |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=KEYWQwAACAAJ |access-date=11 April 2022 |isbn=5875607416 |language= grc,de}}.
The most recent edition of this catalogue is {{cite book |last1=Diels |first1=Hermann |last2=Kranz |first2=Walther |editor-last1=Plamböck |editor-first1=Gert |title=Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker |date=1957 |publisher=Rowohlt |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=KEYWQwAACAAJ |access-date=11 April 2022 |isbn=5875607416 |language= grc,de}}.
{{refend}}
{{refend}}

==== Biography ====
==== Biography ====
{{refbegin|30em}}
{{refbegin|30em}}
Line 113: Line 112:
*'''A2.''' {{cite LotEP |chapter=Parmenides|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A2}}}}
*'''A2.''' {{cite LotEP |chapter=Parmenides|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A2}}}}
*'''A3.''' {{cite LotEP |chapter=Heraclitus|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A3}}}}
*'''A3.''' {{cite LotEP |chapter=Heraclitus|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A3}}}}
*'''A4.''' {{cite book |author = [[Cicero]] | title = [[Academica (Cicero)| Academica]] |at=[http://www.attalus.org/translate/academica2c.html#118 II.118] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A4}}}}
*'''A4.''' {{cite book |author = [[Cicero]] | title = [[Academica (Cicero)|Academica]] |at=[http://www.attalus.org/translate/academica2c.html#118 II.118] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A4}}}}
*'''A5.''' {{cite LotEP |chapter=Empedocles|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A5}}}}
*'''A5.''' {{cite LotEP |chapter=Empedocles|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A5}}}}
*'''A6.''' {{cite book |author =Pseudo-[[Lucian]] | title = Macrobii |url=http://www.attalus.org/translate/macrobii.html| at=[http://www.attalus.org/translate/macrobii.html#20 20] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A6}}}}
*'''A6.''' {{cite book |author =Pseudo-[[Lucian]] | title = Macrobii |url=http://www.attalus.org/translate/macrobii.html| at=[http://www.attalus.org/translate/macrobii.html#20 20] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A6}}}}
Line 121: Line 120:
*'''A10.''' {{cite book |author = [[Iamblichus]] | title = Iamblichi Theologoumena arithmeticae | language=la |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A10}}}}
*'''A10.''' {{cite book |author = [[Iamblichus]] | title = Iamblichi Theologoumena arithmeticae | language=la |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A10}}}}
{{refend}}
{{refend}}

==== Apothegems ====
==== Apothegems ====
{{refbegin|30em}}
{{refbegin|30em}}
*'''A11.''' {{cite book |author = [[Plutarch]] | title = [[Moralia]] | chapter = Sayings of Kings and Commanders |chapter-url=http://www.attalus.org/translate/sayings1.html |at= [[Stephanus pagination|Stephanus]] p.[http://www.attalus.org/translate/sayings1.html#175 175c] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A11}}}}
*'''A11.''' {{cite book |author = [[Plutarch]] | title = [[Moralia]] | chapter = Sayings of Kings and Commanders |chapter-url=http://www.attalus.org/translate/sayings1.html |at= [[Stephanus pagination|Stephanus]] p.[http://www.attalus.org/translate/sayings1.html#175 175c] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A11}}}}
*'''A12.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aristotle]] | title = [[Rhetoric (Aristotle) | Rhetoric]] | at = [[Bekker numbering|Bekker]] [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.%20Rh.%201399b 1399b]| language=en |ref={{sfnref |DK 21A12}}}}
*'''A12.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aristotle]] | title = [[Rhetoric (Aristotle)|Rhetoric]] | at = [[Bekker numbering|Bekker]] [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.%20Rh.%201399b 1399b]| language=en |ref={{sfnref |DK 21A12}}}}
*'''A13.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aristotle]] | title = [[Rhetoric (Aristotle) | Rhetoric]] | at = [[Bekker numbering|Bekker]] [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.%20Rh.%201400b 1400b]| language=en |ref={{sfnref |DK 21A13}}}}
*'''A13.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aristotle]] | title = [[Rhetoric (Aristotle)|Rhetoric]] | at = [[Bekker numbering|Bekker]] [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.%20Rh.%201400b 1400b]| language=en |ref={{sfnref |DK 21A13}}}}
*'''A14.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aristotle]] | title = [[Rhetoric (Aristotle) | Rhetoric]] | at = [[Bekker numbering|Bekker]] [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.%20Rh.%201377a 1377a]| language=en |ref={{sfnref |DK 21A14}}}}
*'''A14.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aristotle]] | title = [[Rhetoric (Aristotle)|Rhetoric]] | at = [[Bekker numbering|Bekker]] [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.%20Rh.%201377a 1377a]| language=en |ref={{sfnref |DK 21A14}}}}
*'''A15.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aristotle]] | title = [[Metaphysics (Aristotle) | Metaphysics]] | at = [[Bekker numbering|Bekker]] [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.%20Rh.%201399b 1399b]| language=en |ref={{sfnref |DK 21A15}}}}
*'''A15.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aristotle]] | title = [[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]] | at = [[Bekker numbering|Bekker]] [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.%20Rh.%201399b 1399b]| language=en |ref={{sfnref |DK 21A15}}}}
*'''A16.''' {{cite book |author = [[Plutarch]] | title = [[Moralia]] | chapter= On Compliancy | at=[http://penelope.uchicago.edu/Thayer/E/Roman/Texts/Plutarch/Moralia/De_vitioso_pudore*.html#5 530e]| language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A16}}}}
*'''A16.''' {{cite book |author = [[Plutarch]] | title = [[Moralia]] | chapter= On Compliancy | at=[http://penelope.uchicago.edu/Thayer/E/Roman/Texts/Plutarch/Moralia/De_vitioso_pudore*.html#5 530e]| language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A16}}}}
*'''A17.''' {{cite book |author = [[Plutarch]] | title = [[Moralia]] | chapter = On Common Conceptions against the Stoics | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20190715112224/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/p/plutarch/essays/complete.html#chapter4 | archive-date = 2019-07-15 | chapter-url=https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/p/plutarch/essays/complete.html#chapter4 | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A17}}}}
*'''A17.''' {{cite book |author = [[Plutarch]] | title = [[Moralia]] | chapter = On Common Conceptions against the Stoics | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20190715112224/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/p/plutarch/essays/complete.html#chapter4 | archive-date = 2019-07-15 | chapter-url=http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/p/plutarch/essays/complete.html#chapter4 | language=en |url-status = dead |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A17}}}}
{{refend}}
{{refend}}

==== Descriptions of Poems ====
==== Descriptions of Poems ====
{{refbegin|30em}}
{{refbegin|30em}}
*'''A18.''' {{cite LotEP |chapter=Parmenides|section=22|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A18}}}}
*'''A18.''' {{cite LotEP |chapter=Parmenides|section=22|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A18}}}}
*'''A19.''' {{cite LotEP |chapter=Xenophanes|section=18|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A19}}}}
*'''A19.''' {{cite LotEP |chapter=Xenophanes|section=18|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A19}}}}
*'''A20.''' {{cite book |author = [[Strabo]] | title = [[Geography (Strabo) | Geography]] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A20}}}}
*'''A20.''' {{cite book |author = [[Strabo]] | title = [[Geography (Strabo)|Geography]] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A20}}}}
*'''A21.''' {{cite book |author = [[Apuleius]] | title = Florida | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A21}}}}
*'''A21.''' {{cite book |author = [[Apuleius]] | title = Florida | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A21}}}}
*'''A22.''' {{cite book |author = [[Proclus]] | title = Commentary on Hesiod's Works and Days | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A22}}}}
*'''A22.''' {{cite book |author = [[Proclus]] | title = Commentary on Hesiod's Works and Days | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A22}}}}
*'''A23.''' {{cite book | title = [[Scholia]] |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A22}}}}
*'''A23.''' {{cite book | title = [[Scholia]] |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A22}}}}
*'''A24.''' {{cite book |author = [[Arius Didymus]] | title = Doxographi Graeci | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A24}}}}
*'''A24.''' {{cite book |author = [[Arius Didymus]] | title = Doxographi Graeci | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A24}}}}
*'''A25.''' {{cite book |author = [[Cicero]] | title = [[Academica (Cicero)| Academica]] | at=[http://www.attalus.org/translate/academica2b.html#74 II.74] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A25}}}}
*'''A25.''' {{cite book |author = [[Cicero]] | title = [[Academica (Cicero)|Academica]] | at=[http://www.attalus.org/translate/academica2b.html#74 II.74] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A25}}}}
*'''A26.''' {{cite book |author = [[Philo]] | title = [[Philo's works | On Providence]] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A26}}}}
*'''A26.''' {{cite book |author = [[Philo]] | title = [[Philo's works|On Providence]] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A26}}}}
*'''A27.''' {{cite book |author = [[Athenaeus]] | title = [[Deipnosophistae]] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A27}}| at=[http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Ath.+14.32 632cd]}}
*'''A27.''' {{cite book |author = [[Athenaeus]] | title = [[Deipnosophistae]] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A27}}| at=[http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Ath.+14.32 632cd]}}
{{refend}}
{{refend}}
Line 151: Line 152:
*'''A30.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aristotle]] | title = [[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]] | at=[[Bekker numbering|Bekker]] [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.%20Met.%201.986b 986b] |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A30}}}}
*'''A30.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aristotle]] | title = [[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]] | at=[[Bekker numbering|Bekker]] [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Aristot.%20Met.%201.986b 986b] |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A30}}}}
*'''A31.''' {{cite book |author = [[Simplicius of Cilicia]] | title = Commentary on [[Physics (Aristotle)|Aristotle's Physics]] |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A31}}}}
*'''A31.''' {{cite book |author = [[Simplicius of Cilicia]] | title = Commentary on [[Physics (Aristotle)|Aristotle's Physics]] |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A31}}}}
*'''A32.''' {{cite book |author = [[Pseudo-Plutarch]] | title = [[Moralia]] |chapter=Opinions of the Philosophers | at=[https://web.archive.org/web/20181021024551/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/p/plutarch/nature/complete.html#chapter34 Book II.4] |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A32}}}}
*'''A32.''' {{cite book |author = [[Pseudo-Plutarch]] | title = [[Moralia]] |chapter=Opinions of the Philosophers | at=[https://web.archive.org/web/20080730180549/http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/p/plutarch/nature/complete.html#chapter34 Book II.4] |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A32}}}}
*'''A33.''' {{cite wikisource |author = [[Hippolytus of Rome]] | wslink=Ante-Nicene_Fathers/Volume_V/Hippolytus/The_Refutation_of_All_Heresies/Book_I/Part_14 |wspage=Book I.14 |plaintitle = [[Refutation of All Heresies]] |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A33}}}}
*'''A33.''' {{cite wikisource |author = [[Hippolytus of Rome]] | wslink=Ante-Nicene_Fathers/Volume_V/Hippolytus/The_Refutation_of_All_Heresies/Book_I/Part_14 |wspage=Book I.14 |plaintitle = [[Refutation of All Heresies]] |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A33}}}}
*'''A34.''' {{cite book |author = [[Cicero]] | title = [[Academica (Cicero) | Academica]] | at=[http://www.attalus.org/translate/academica2c.html#118 II.118] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A34}}}}
*'''A34.''' {{cite book |author = [[Cicero]] | title = [[Academica (Cicero)|Academica]] | at=[http://www.attalus.org/translate/academica2c.html#118 II.118] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21A34}}}}
*'''A35.''' {{cite book |author = Pseudo-[[Galen]] | title = History of Philosophy |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A35}}}}
*'''A35.''' {{cite book |author = Pseudo-[[Galen]] | title = History of Philosophy |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A35}}}}
*'''A36-46.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aetius (philosopher)|Aetius]] | title = Placita |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A33-46}}}}
*'''A36-46.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aetius (philosopher)|Aetius]] | title = Placita |language=en|ref={{sfnref|DK 21A33-46}}}}
Line 176: Line 177:
*'''B9.''' {{cite book | title = [[Etymologicum Genuinum]]| at= [https://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/morph?l=ghras&la=greek#Perseus:text:1999.04.0057:entry=gh=ras2-contents γῆρας] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21B9}}}}
*'''B9.''' {{cite book | title = [[Etymologicum Genuinum]]| at= [https://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/morph?l=ghras&la=greek#Perseus:text:1999.04.0057:entry=gh=ras2-contents γῆρας] | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21B9}}}}
{{refend}}
{{refend}}

==== Fragments - Silloi ====
==== Fragments - Silloi ====
{{refbegin|30em}}
{{refbegin|30em}}
Line 192: Line 194:
*'''B22.''' {{cite book |author = [[Athenaeus]] | title = [[Deipnosophistae]] |at=2.54e | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21B22}}}}
*'''B22.''' {{cite book |author = [[Athenaeus]] | title = [[Deipnosophistae]] |at=2.54e | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21B22}}}}
{{refend}}
{{refend}}

==== Fragments - On Nature ====
==== Fragments - On Nature ====
{{refbegin|30em}}
{{refbegin|30em}}
Line 214: Line 217:
*'''B41.''' {{cite book |author = [[John Tzetzes]] | title = Scholia to [[Dionysius Periegetes]] | at = 940 | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21B41}}}}
*'''B41.''' {{cite book |author = [[John Tzetzes]] | title = Scholia to [[Dionysius Periegetes]] | at = 940 | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21B41}}}}
*'''B42.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aelius Herodianus]] | title = On peculiar style | at= 41.5 | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21B42}}}}
*'''B42.''' {{cite book |author = [[Aelius Herodianus]] | title = On peculiar style | at= 41.5 | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21B42}}}}
*'''B45.''' {{cite book |title = Scholia to [[Hippocratic_Corpus#Epidemics_1|On Epidemics]] | at = 1.13.3 | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21B45}}}}
*'''B45.''' {{cite book |title = Scholia to [[Hippocratic Corpus#Epidemics 1|On Epidemics]] | at = 1.13.3 | language=en |ref={{sfnref|DK 21B45}}}}
{{refend}}
{{refend}}


Line 242: Line 245:
{{refbegin|30em}}
{{refbegin|30em}}
* {{cite book |last1=Barnes |first1=Jonathan |title=The Presocratic Philosophers |date=1982 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-415-05079-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=wrNzVF5julgC |access-date=13 April 2022 |language=en}}
* {{cite book |last1=Barnes |first1=Jonathan |title=The Presocratic Philosophers |date=1982 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-415-05079-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=wrNzVF5julgC |access-date=13 April 2022 |language=en}}
* {{cite book |last=Dalby |first=Andrew |title=Rediscovering Homer |publisher=Norton |place=New York, London |year=2006 |isbn=0-393-05788-7 |url-access=registration |url=https://archive.org/details/rediscoveringhom00dalb |page=123}}
* {{cite book |last=Dalby |first=Andrew |title=Rediscovering Homer |publisher=Norton |place=New York, London |year=2006 |isbn=0-393-05788-7 |page=123 |url=https://archive.org/details/rediscoveringhom00dalb |url-access=registration}}
* {{cite book |last=Edwards |first=M. J. | url = https://grbs.library.duke.edu/article/view/3781 | format = PDF | title = Xenophanes Christianus? | journal = [[Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies]] | year = 2005 | volume = 32 | issue = 3 | page = 220 | issn = 0017-3916 | oclc = 8162351763 | isbn = 9781351219143| publisher = [[Duke University Press]] | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20140301104327/https://grbs.library.duke.edu/article/download/3781/5651 | archive-date = March 1, 2014 | url-status = live}}
* {{cite journal |last=Edwards |first=M. J. |url=https://grbs.library.duke.edu/index.php/grbs/article/view/3781/5651 |title=Xenophanes Christianus? |journal=[[Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies]] |year=2005 |volume=32 |issue=3 |page=220 |issn=0017-3916 |oclc=8162351763 |isbn=9781351219143| publisher=[[Duke University Press]] |archive-date=March 1, 2014 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140301104327/https://grbs.library.duke.edu/article/download/3781/5651 |url-status=live}}
* {{cite book |last=Johansen |first=Karsten Friis |publisher=Taylor & Francis |year=1999 |isbn=9780203979808 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3waGV4BJmfQC&pg=PA49 |title=A history of ancient philosophy: from the beginnings to Augustine}}
* {{cite book |last=Johansen |first=Karsten Friis |publisher=Taylor & Francis |year=1999 |isbn=9780203979808 |title=A history of ancient philosophy: from the beginnings to Augustine |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3waGV4BJmfQC&pg=PA49}}
*{{cite SEP |url-id=xenophanes |title=Xenophanes |last=Lesher |first=James| date=2019}}
*{{cite SEP |url-id=xenophanes |title=Xenophanes |last=Lesher |first=James| date=2019}}
*{{cite encyclopedia|last=Lesher |first=James |title=Xenophanes |date=2021 |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |edition=Summer 2021 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/xenophanes/ |access-date=2022-06-12}}
*{{cite book |last=Luchte |first=James |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FQixkgEACAAJ |title=Early Greek Thought: Before the Dawn |year=2011 |publisher=Bloomsbury Publishing |location=London |isbn=978-0567353313}}
*{{cite book |last=Luchte |first=James |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FQixkgEACAAJ |title=Early Greek Thought: Before the Dawn |year=2011 |publisher=Bloomsbury Publishing |location=London |isbn=978-0567353313}}
*{{cite book |last1=Mackenzie |first1=Tom |chapter=Xenophanes|title=Poetry and poetics in the Presocratic philosophers : reading Xenophanes, Parmenides and Empedocles as literature |date=2021 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |location=Cambridge, United Kingdom |isbn=9781108843935 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XPQgEAAAQBAJ|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XPQgEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA24|pages=24–64}}
*{{cite book |last1=Mackenzie |first1=Tom |chapter=Xenophanes|title=Poetry and poetics in the Presocratic philosophers : reading Xenophanes, Parmenides and Empedocles as literature |date=2021 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |location=Cambridge, United Kingdom |isbn=9781108843935 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XPQgEAAAQBAJ|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XPQgEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA24|pages=24–64}}
*{{cite journal | url = https://scielo.conicyt.cl/pdf/byzantion/n29/art04.pdf | title = La tradición en la teología de Jenófanes | trans-title = Tradition in Xenophanes' theology | last1= Meza |first1 = Carlos Gustavo Carrasco | journal = Byzantion nea hellás | issn = 0718-8471 | issue = 29 | location = Santiago | year = 2010 | doi = 10.4067/S0718-84712010000100004 | pages = 55, 57 | language = es, en | oclc = 7179329409 | publisher = [[University of Chile]] | doi-broken-date = 31 December 2022 | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20200917100159/https://byzantion.uchile.cl/index.php/RBNH/article/view/18106 | archive-date = September 17, 2020 | url-status = live}}
*{{cite journal |url=https://scielo.conicyt.cl/pdf/byzantion/n29/art04.pdf |title=La tradición en la teología de Jenófanes |trans-title=Tradition in Xenophanes' theology |last1=Meza |first1=Carlos Gustavo Carrasco |journal=Byzantion nea hellás |issn=0718-8471 |issue=29 |location=Santiago |year=2010 |doi=10.4067/S0718-84712010000100004 |pages=55, 57 |language=es, en |oclc=7179329409 |publisher=[[University of Chile]] |doi-broken-date=31 January 2024 |url-status=live |archive-date=September 17, 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200917100159/https://byzantion.uchile.cl/index.php/RBNH/article/view/18106}}
*{{cite book |last1=Mourelatos |first1=Alexander |chapter=The Cloud - Astrophysics of Xenophanes and Ionian Material Monism |title=The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy |date=2008 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford |isbn=978-0-19-514687-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=14muxtEiBG0C |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=14muxtEiBG0C&pg=PA134|pages=134–168}}
*{{cite book |last1=Mourelatos |first1=Alexander |chapter=The Cloud - Astrophysics of Xenophanes and Ionian Material Monism |title=The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy |date=2008 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford |isbn=978-0-19-514687-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=14muxtEiBG0C |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=14muxtEiBG0C&pg=PA134 |pages=134–168}}
*{{cite book |last1=Osborne |first1=Catherine |title=Presocratic Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction |date=22 April 2004 |publisher=OUP Oxford |isbn=978-0-19-157822-9 |pages=61–79 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=4QO_2YHyv4cC |access-date=13 April 2022 |language=en}}
*{{cite book |last1=Osborne |first1=Catherine |title=Presocratic Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction |date=22 April 2004 |publisher=OUP Oxford |isbn=978-0-19-157822-9 |pages=61–79 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=4QO_2YHyv4cC |access-date=13 April 2022 |language=en}}
*{{cite book |last1=Warren |first1=James |title=Presocratics |date=2007 |publisher=Acumen |isbn=978-1-84465-091-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-EAqAQAAMAAJ |access-date=14 April 2022 |language=en}}
*{{cite book |last1=Warren |first1=James |title=Presocratics |date=2007 |publisher=Acumen |isbn=978-1-84465-091-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-EAqAQAAMAAJ |access-date=14 April 2022 |language=en}}
Line 275: Line 279:
[[Category:470s BC deaths]]
[[Category:470s BC deaths]]
[[Category:570s BC births]]
[[Category:570s BC births]]
[[Category:6th-century BC Greek people]]
[[Category:6th-century BC Greek philosophers]]
[[Category:6th-century BC philosophers]]
[[Category:6th-century BC poets]]
[[Category:6th-century BC poets]]
[[Category:5th-century BC Greek people]]
[[Category:5th-century BC Greek philosophers]]
[[Category:5th-century BC philosophers]]
[[Category:5th-century BC poets]]
[[Category:5th-century BC poets]]
[[Category:Ancient Colophonians]]
[[Category:Ancient Colophonians]]

Latest revision as of 22:17, 8 May 2024

Xenophanes
Fictionalized portrait of Xenophanes from a 17th-century engraving
Bornc. 570 BC
Colophon, Ionian League
(modern-day Değirmendere, İzmir, Turkey)
Diedc. 478 BC (aged c. 92)
EraPre-Socratic philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
Main interests
Social criticism
Kataphasis
Natural philosophy
Epistemology
Notable ideas
Religious polytheistic views as human projections
Earth and water is the arche
The distinction between knowledge and mere true belief.

Xenophanes of Colophon (/zəˈnɒfənz/ zə-NOF-ə-neez;[1][2] Ancient Greek: Ξενοφάνης ὁ Κολοφώνιος [ksenopʰánɛːs ho kolopʰɔ̌ːnios]; c. 570 – c. 478 BC) was a Greek philosopher, theologian, poet, and critic of Homer from Ionia who travelled throughout the Greek-speaking world in early Classical Antiquity.

As a poet, Xenophanes was known for his critical style, writing poems that are considered among the first satires. He also composed elegiac couplets that criticised his society's traditional values of wealth, excesses, and athletic victories. He also criticised Homer and the other poets in his works for representing the gods as foolish or morally weak. His poems have not survived intact; only fragments of some of his work survive in quotations by later philosophers and literary critics.

Xenophanes is seen as one of the most important pre-Socratic philosophers. A highly original thinker, Xenophanes sought explanations for physical phenomena such as clouds or rainbows without references to divine or mythological explanations, but instead based on first principles. He also distinguished between different forms of knowledge and belief, an early instance of epistemology. Later philosophers such as the Eleatics and the Pyrrhonists also saw Xenophanes as the founder of their doctrines, and interpreted his work in terms of those doctrines, although modern scholarship disputes these claims.

Life

[edit]

The Ancient biographer Diogenes Laertius reports that Xenophanes was born in Colophon, a city that once existed in Ionia, in present-day Turkey.[3][a] Laertius says that Xenophanes is said to have flourished during the 60th Olympiad (540–537 BC),[b] and modern scholars generally place his birth some time around 570-560 BC.[3] His surviving work refers to Thales, Epimenides, and Pythagoras,[c] and he himself is mentioned in the writings of Heraclitus and Epicharmus.[d]

By his own surviving account,[e] he was an itinerant poet who left his native land at the age of 25 and then lived 67 years in other Greek lands, dying at or after the age of 92.[3] Although ancient testimony notes that he buried his sons, there is little other biographical information about him or his family that can be reliably ascertained.[3]

It is considered likely Xenophanes' physical theories were influenced by the Milesians. For instance, his theory that the rainbow is clouds is on one interpretation seen as a response to Anaximenes's theory that the rainbow is light reflected off of clouds.[4]

Poems

[edit]
Xenophanes characterised his travels as "tossing up and down[f]" Ancient Greece in the archaic period. His travels took him from Colophon, Ionia in present-day Turkey as far as colonies in Magna Graecia in present-day Italy[3]

Knowledge of Xenophanes' views comes from fragments of his poetry that survive as quotations by later Greek writers. Unlike other pre-socratic philosophers such as Heraclitus or Parmenides, who only wrote one work, Xenophanes wrote a variety of poems, and no two of the fragments can positively be identified as belonging to the same text.[5] According to Diogenes Laertius,[g] Xenophanes wrote a poem on the foundation of Colophon and Elea, which ran to approximately 2000 lines.[5] Later testimony also suggests that his collection of satires was assembled in at least five books.[6] Although many later sources attribute a poem titled "On Nature" to Xenophanes, modern scholars doubt this label, as it was likely a name given by scholars at the Library of Alexandria to works written by philosophers that Aristotle had identified as "phusikoi" who studied nature.[5]

Satires

[edit]

The satires are called Silloi by late writers, and this name may go back to Xenophanes himself, but it may originate in the fact that the Pyrrhonist philosopher Timon of Phlius, the "sillographer" (3rd century BC), put much of his own satire upon other philosophers into the mouth of Xenophanes, one of the few philosophers Timon praises in his work.[7]

Xenophanes' surviving writings display a skepticism that became more commonly expressed during the fourth century BC. Several of the philosophical fragments are derived from commentators on Homer. He aimed his critique at the polytheistic religious views of earlier Greek poets and of his own contemporaries

To judge from these later accounts,[h] his elegiac and iambic poetry criticized and satirized a wide range of ideas, including Homer and Hesiod,[8] the belief in the pantheon of anthropomorphic gods and the Greeks' veneration of athleticism.

On Nature

[edit]

There is no good authority that says that Xenophanes specifically wrote a philosophical poem.[7] John Burnet says that "The oldest reference to a poem Περὶ φύσεως is in the Geneva scholium on Iliad xxi. 196,[i] and this goes back to Crates of Mallus. We must remember that such titles are of later date, and Xenophanes had been given a place among philosophers long before the time of Crates. All we can say, therefore, is that the Pergamene librarians gave the title Περὶ φύσεως to some poem of Xenophanes." However, even if Xenophanes never wrote a specific poem title On Nature, many of the surviving fragments deal with topics in natural philosophy such as clouds or rainbows, and it is thus likely that the philosophical remarks of Xenophanes were expressed incidentally in his satires.[7]

Philosophy

[edit]

Although Xenophanes has traditionally been interpreted in terms of the Eleatics and Skeptics who were influenced by him and saw him as their predecessor and founder, modern scholarship has revealed him to be a highly original and distinct philosopher whose philosophy extends well beyond the influence he had on later philosophical schools.[9] As a social critic, Xenophanes composed poems on proper behavior at a symposium and criticized the cultural glorification of athletes.[9] Xenophanes sought to reform the understanding of divine nature by casting doubt on Greek mythology as relayed by Hesiod and Homer, in order to make it more consistent with notions of piety from Ancient Greek religion.[9] He composed natural explanations for phenomena such as the formation of clouds and rainbows rather than myths,[9] satirizing traditional religious views of his time as human projections.[10] As an early thinker in epistemology, he drew distinctions between the ideas of knowledge and belief as opposed to truth, which he believed was only possible for the gods.[9]

Social criticism

[edit]
6th century BC depiction of an Ancient Greek symposium. Xenophanes criticized these drinking parties as they were celebrated in his time for their excesses and failures to honor the gods.[9]

Xenophanes wrote a number of elegiac poems on proper conduct at a symposium,[9] the Ancient Greek drinking parties that were held to commemorate athletic or poetic victories, or to welcome young men into aristocratic society. The surviving fragments stress the importance of piety and honor to the gods,[j] and they discourage drunkenness[k] and intemperance, endorsing moderation and criticism of luxury and excess.[l] Xenophanes also rejected the value of athletic victories, stating that cultivating wisdom was more important.[m][9]

Divine Nature

[edit]

Orphism and Pythagorean philosophy introduced into the Greek spirituality the notions of guilt and pureness, causing a dichotomic belief between the divine soul and the mortal body. This doctrine is in contrast with the traditional religions as espoused by Homer and Hesiod.[11] God moves all things, but he is thought to be immobile, characterized by oneness[n][12] and unicity, eternity,[o] and a spiritual nature which is bodiless and isn't anthropomorphic.[p] He has a free will and is the Highest Good, he embodies the beauty of the moral perfection and of the absence of sin.[11]

Xenophanes espoused a belief that "God is one, supreme among gods and men, and not like mortals in body or in mind." He maintained that there was one greatest God. God is one eternal being, spherical in form, comprehending all things within himself, is the absolute mind and thought,[q] therefore is intelligent, and moves all things, but bears no resemblance to human nature either in body or mind. While Xenophanes rejected Homeric theology, he did not question the presence of a divine entity; rather his philosophy was a critique on Ancient Greek writers and their conception of divinity.[13] Regarding Xenophanes' positive theology five key concepts about God can be formed. God is: beyond human morality, does not resemble human form, cannot die or be born (God is divine thus eternal), no divine hierarchy exists, and God does not intervene in human affairs.[13]

Natural Philosophy

[edit]
Xenophanes was likely the first philosopher to offer a naturalistic rather than a mythological explanation for St. Elmo's Fire.[14]

Xenophanes' understanding of divine nature as separate and uninvolved in human affairs motivated him to come up with naturalistic explanations for physical phenomena.[9]

Xenophanes was likely the first philosopher to come up with an explanation for the manifestation of St. Elmo's fire that appears on the masts of ships when they pass through clouds during a thunderstorm. Although the actual phenomenon behind St. Elmo's fire would not be understood until the discovery of static electricity in the modern era, Xenophanes' explanation, which attempted to explain the glow as being caused by agitations of small droplets of clouds[r] was unique in the ancient world.[14]

In Xenophanes' cosmology, there is only one boundary to the universe,[15] the one "seen by our feet".[s] Xenophanes believed that the earth extended infinitely far down, as well as infinitely far in every direction.[15] A consequence of his belief in an infinitely extended earth was that rather than having the sun pass under the earth at sunset, Xenophanes believed that the sun and the moon traveled along a straight line westward,[t] after which point a new sun or moon would be reconstituted after an eclipse.[u][15] While this potentially infinite series of suns and moons traveling would likely be considered objectionable to modern scientists,[15] this means that Xenophanes understood the sun and moon as a "type" of object that appeared in the sky, rather than a specific individual object that reappeared every new day.[15]

Xenophanes concluded from his examination of fossils of sea creatures that were found above land[v] that water once must have covered all of the Earth's surface.[16] He used this evidence to conclude that the arche or cosmic principle of the universe was a tide flowing in and out between wet and dry, or earth (γῆ) and water (ὕδωρ). These two extreme states would alternate between one another, and with the alternation human life would become extinct, then regenerate (or vice versa depending on the dominant form).[17] The argument can be considered a rebuke to Anaximenes' air theory.[17] The idea of alternating states and human life perishing and coming back suggests he believed in the principle of causation, another distinguishing step that Xenophanes takes away from Ancient philosophical traditions to ones based more on scientific observation.[16][clarification needed] This use of evidence was an important step in advancing from simply stating an idea to backing it up by evidence and observation.[17]

Epistemology

[edit]

Xenophanes is one of the first philosophers to show interest in epistemological questions as well as metaphysical ones. He held that there actually exists an objective truth in reality,[w] but that as mere mortals, humans are unable to know it.[x] He is also credited with being one of the first philosophers to distinguish between true belief and knowledge,[y] as well as acknowledge the prospect that one can think he knows something but not really know it.[18]

His verses on skepticism are quoted by Sextus Empiricus as follows:

Yet, with regard to the gods and what I declare about all things:
No man has seen what is clear nor will any man ever know it.
Nay, for even should he chance to affirm what is really existent,
He himself knoweth it not; for all is swayed by opining.[z]

Due to the lack of whole works by Xenophanes, his views are difficult to interpret, so that the implication of knowing being something deeper ("a clearer truth") may have special implications, or it may mean that you cannot know something just by looking at it.[18] It is known that the most and widest variety of evidence was considered by Xenophanes to be the surest way to prove a theory.[16]

Legacy and influence

[edit]

Xenophanes's influence has been interpreted variously as "the founder of epistemology, a poet and rhapsode and not a philosopher at all, the first skeptic, the first empiricist, a rationalist theologian, a reformer of religion, and more besides."[19] Karl Popper read Xenophanes as an early precursor of critical rationalism, saying that it is possible to act only on the basis of working hypotheses—we may act as if we knew the truth, as long as we know that this is extremely unlikely.[20]

Influence on Eleatics

[edit]

Many later ancient accounts associate Xenophanes with the Greek colony in the Italian city of Elea, either as the author of a poem on the founding of that city,[aa] or as the founder of the Eleatic school of philosophy,[ab] or as the teacher of Parmenides of Elea.[ac] Others associate him with Pythagoreanism. However, modern scholars generally believe that there is little historical or philosophical justification for these associations between Pythagoras, Xenophanes, and Parmenides as is oft alleged in succession of the so-called "Italian school".[3] It had similarly been common since antiquity to see Xenophanes as the teacher of Zeno of Elea, the colleague of Parmenides, but common opinion today is likewise that this is false.[21]

In his ninety-second year he was still, we have seen, leading a wandering life, which is hardly consistent with the statement that he settled at Elea and founded a school there, especially if we are to think of him as spending his last days at Hieron's court. It is very remarkable that no ancient writer expressly says he ever was at Elea, and all the evidence we have seems inconsistent with his having settled there at all.[22]

Influence on Pyrrhonism

[edit]

Xenophanes is sometimes considered the first skeptic in Western philosophy.[23][ad] Xenophanes's alleged skepticism can also be seen as a precursor to Pyrrhonism. Sextus quotes Pyrrho's follower Timon as praising Xenophanes and dedicating his satires to him, and giving him as an example of somebody who is not a perfect skeptic (like Pyrrho), but who is forgivably close to it.[24]

Eusebius quoting Aristocles of Messene says that Xenophanes was the founder of a line of philosophy that culminated in Pyrrhonism. This line begins with Xenophanes and goes through Parmenides, Melissus of Samos, Zeno of Elea, Leucippus, Democritus, Protagoras, Nessos of Chios, Metrodorus of Chios, Diogenes of Smyrna, Anaxarchus, and finally Pyrrho.[ae]

Pantheism

[edit]

Because of his development of the concept of a "one god greatest among gods and men," Xenophanes is often seen as one of the first monotheists in Western philosophy of religion. However, the same referenced quotation refers to multiple "gods" who the supreme God is greater than.[25] This god "shakes all things" by the power of his thought alone. Differently from the human creatures, God has the power to give "immediate execution" (in Greek: to phren) and make effective his cognitive faculty (in Greek: nous).[af]

The thought of Xenophanes was summarized as monolatrous and pantheistic by the ancient doxographies of Aristotle, Cicero, Diogenes Laertius, Sextus Empiricus, and Plutarch. More particularly, Aristotle's Metaphysics summarized his view as "the All is God."[ag] The pseudo-Aristotlelian treatise On Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias also contains a significant testimony of his teachings.[ah] Pierre Bayle considered Xenophanes views similar to Spinoza.[26] Physicist and philosopher Max Bernhard Weinstein specifically identified Xenophanes as one of the earliest pandeists.[ai]

Xenophanes's view of an impersonal god seemed to influence the pre-socratic Empedocles, who viewed god as an incorporeal mind.[28] However, Empedocles called Xenophanes's view that Earth is flat and extends downward forever to be foolishness.[29][30]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ (DK 21A1)
  2. ^ Diogenes Laertius, ix. 18-20 (DK 21A1)
  3. ^ Diogenes Laertius
  4. ^ Diogenes Laertius, ix. 1; Aristotle, Metaphysics
  5. ^ (DK 21B8)
  6. ^ (DK 21B8)
  7. ^ DK 28A1
  8. ^ Diogenes Laertius, ix. 18-20 (DK 21A1)
  9. ^ DK 21B30
  10. ^ To hymn the praises of the Gods; and so / With pure libations and well-order'd vows / To win from them the power to act with justice / For this comes from the favour of the Gods;(DK 21B1)
  11. ^ And never let a man a goblet take / And first pour in the wine; but let the water / Come first, and after that, then add the wine.(DK 21B5)
  12. ^ They learnt all sorts of useless foolishness / From the effeminate Lydians, while they / Were held in bondage to sharp tyranny / They went into the forum richly clad / In purple garments, in numerous companies / Whose strength was not less than a thousand men / Boasting of hair luxuriously dress'd / Dripping with costly and sweet-smelling oils.(DK 21B3)
  13. ^ For wisdom far exceeds in real value / The bodily strength of man, or horses' speed;/ But the mob judges of such things at random; / Though 'tis not right to prefer strength to sense:(DK 21B2)
  14. ^ "One god, the greatest among gods and men, neither in form like unto mortals nor in thought." (DK 21B23)
  15. ^ DK 21B26
  16. ^ DK 21B14-15, DK 21B16
  17. ^ Diogenes Laertius, ix. 18-20 (DK 21A1)
  18. ^ DK 21A39:"Those star-like apparitions mariners call the Dioskouroi—they are in reality clouds: small ones that glow because of some agitation."
  19. ^ DK 21A28
  20. ^ DK 21 A41a
  21. ^ DK 21 A41a
  22. ^ DK 21A33
  23. ^ (DK 21B18)
  24. ^ DK 21B34
  25. ^ DK 21B34
  26. ^ quoted by Sextus Empiricus,(DK 21B34)
  27. ^ DK 28A1
  28. ^ A8,30,36
  29. ^ A2, A30, A31
  30. ^ DK 21B49
  31. ^ DK 21A49
  32. ^ DK 21B25
  33. ^ DK 21A30
  34. ^ DK 21A28
  35. ^ "Pandeistisch ist, wenn der Eleate Xenophanes (aus Kolophon um 580-492 v. Chr.) von Gott gesagt haben soll: "Er ist ganz und gar Geist und Gedanke und ewig", "er sieht ganz und gar, er denkt ganz und gar, er hört ganz und gar."[27]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ "Xenophanes" entry in Collins English Dictionary.
  2. ^ Sound file
  3. ^ a b c d e f Lesher 1992, p. 3-4.
  4. ^ Xenophanes (January 2001). James H. Lesher (ed.). Fragments. University of Toronto Press. p. 140. ISBN 9780802085085.
  5. ^ a b c Mackenzie 2021, p. 24-27.
  6. ^ DK 21B21a.
  7. ^ a b c Burnet 1892.
  8. ^ Barnes 1982, p. 40.
  9. ^ a b c d e f g h i Lesher 2019.
  10. ^ Johansen 1999, p. 49.
  11. ^ a b Meza 2010, p. 55-57.
  12. ^ Burnet 1892, p. 119.
  13. ^ a b McKirahan 1994, p. 60-62.
  14. ^ a b Mourelatos 2008, p. 134.
  15. ^ a b c d e Mourelatos 2008, p. 138-139.
  16. ^ a b c McKirahan 1994, p. 66.
  17. ^ a b c McKirahan 1994, p. 65-66.
  18. ^ a b Osborne 2004, p. 66-67.
  19. ^ Is God In the Clouds?: A Note on Xenophanes by Michael Sevel
  20. ^ Popper 1998, p. 46.
  21. ^ Lesher 1992, p. 102.
  22. ^ Burnet 1892, p. 115.
  23. ^ Xenophanes' Scepticism by James H. Lesher, Phronesis Vol. 23, No. 1 (1978), pp. 1-21
  24. ^ A. A. Long. From Epicurus to Epictetus. p. 86.
  25. ^ Lesher 2021.
  26. ^ Bayle, Critical Dictionary, p. 574
  27. ^ Weinstein 1910, p. 231.
  28. ^ "Empedocles" Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1961) by Charles Kahn, p. 498
  29. ^ DK 21B28
  30. ^ DK31B39

Bibliography

[edit]

Ancient Primary Sources

[edit]

In the Diels-Kranz numbering for testimony and fragments of Pre-Socratic philosophy, Xenophanes is catalogued as number 21.

The most recent edition of this catalogue is Diels, Hermann; Kranz, Walther (1957). Plamböck, Gert (ed.). Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (in Ancient Greek and German). Rowohlt. ISBN 5875607416. Retrieved 11 April 2022..

Biography

[edit]

Apothegems

[edit]

Descriptions of Poems

[edit]

Doctrines

[edit]

Fragments - Elegies

[edit]

Fragments - Silloi

[edit]

Fragments - On Nature

[edit]

Imitation

[edit]

Modern Criticism

[edit]

Modern Scholarship

[edit]

Translations of the Fragments with Commentary

[edit]

Extended Studies and Reviews

[edit]

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]