Jump to content

Ranked voting: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
No edit summary
Line 1: Line 1:
{{multiple image
{{More sources needed|date=July 2024}}{{multiple image
| width = 160
| width = 160
| align = right
| align = right
Line 30: Line 30:
Interest in ranked voting continued throughout the 19th century. Danish pioneer [[Carl Christoffer Georg Andræ|Carl Andræ]] formulated the [[single transferable vote]] (STV), which was adopted by his native [[Denmark]] in 1855. Condorcet had previously considered the single-winner version of it, the [[Instant-runoff voting|instant-runoff]] system, but immediately rejected it as [[Pathological (mathematics)#In voting|pathological]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Nanson |first=E. J. |date=1882 |title=Methods of election: Ware's Method |url=https://archive.org/details/transactionsproc1719roya/page/206 |journal=Transactions and Proceedings of the Royal Society of Victoria |volume=19 |pages=206 |quote=The method was, however, mentioned by Condorcet, but only to be condemned.}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Condorcet |first=Jean-Antoine-Nicolas de Caritat |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=d0cwAAAAYAAJ&q=Oeuvres+de+Condorcet%2C+Volume+13&pg=PA243 |title=Complete Works of Condorcet |date=1788 |volume=13 |publication-date=1804 |pages=243 |language=fr |section=On the Constitution and the Functions of Provincial Assemblies |quote=En effet, lorsqu'il y a plus de trois concurrents, le véritable vœu de la pluralité peut être pour un candidat qui n'ait eu aucune des voix dans le premier scrutin.}}</ref>
Interest in ranked voting continued throughout the 19th century. Danish pioneer [[Carl Christoffer Georg Andræ|Carl Andræ]] formulated the [[single transferable vote]] (STV), which was adopted by his native [[Denmark]] in 1855. Condorcet had previously considered the single-winner version of it, the [[Instant-runoff voting|instant-runoff]] system, but immediately rejected it as [[Pathological (mathematics)#In voting|pathological]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Nanson |first=E. J. |date=1882 |title=Methods of election: Ware's Method |url=https://archive.org/details/transactionsproc1719roya/page/206 |journal=Transactions and Proceedings of the Royal Society of Victoria |volume=19 |pages=206 |quote=The method was, however, mentioned by Condorcet, but only to be condemned.}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Condorcet |first=Jean-Antoine-Nicolas de Caritat |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=d0cwAAAAYAAJ&q=Oeuvres+de+Condorcet%2C+Volume+13&pg=PA243 |title=Complete Works of Condorcet |date=1788 |volume=13 |publication-date=1804 |pages=243 |language=fr |section=On the Constitution and the Functions of Provincial Assemblies |quote=En effet, lorsqu'il y a plus de trois concurrents, le véritable vœu de la pluralité peut être pour un candidat qui n'ait eu aucune des voix dans le premier scrutin.}}</ref>


Theoretical exploration of electoral processes was revived by a 1948 paper from [[Duncan Black]]<ref name="black2">Duncan Black, "On the Rationale of Group Decision-making" (1948).</ref> and [[Kenneth Arrow]]'s investigations into [[social choice theory]], a branch of [[welfare economics]] that extends [[Decision theory|rational choice]] to include community decision-making processes.
Theoretical exploration of electoral processes was revived by a 1948 paper from [[Duncan Black]]<ref name="black2">Duncan Black, "On the Rationale of Group Decision-making" (1948).</ref> and [[Kenneth Arrow]]'s investigations into [[social choice theory]], a branch of [[welfare economics]] that extends [[Decision theory|rational choice]] to include community decision-making processes.<ref name="Arrow 1963232">{{Cite book |last=Arrow |first=Kenneth Joseph Arrow |url=http://cowles.yale.edu/sites/default/files/files/pub/mon/m12-2-all.pdf |title=Social Choice and Individual Values |date=1963 |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=978-0300013641 |archive-url=https://ghostarchive.org/archive/20221009/http://cowles.yale.edu/sites/default/files/files/pub/mon/m12-2-all.pdf |archive-date=2022-10-09 |url-status=live}}</ref>


=== Adoption ===
=== Adoption ===
[[Plurality voting]] is the most common voting system, and has been in widespread use since the earliest [[Democracy|democracies]].{{Cn|date=July 2024}}
[[Plurality voting]] is the most common voting system, and has been in widespread use since the earliest [[Democracy|democracies]].{{Cn|date=July 2024}}


The [[single transferable vote]] (STV) system was first invented by [[Carl Christoffer Georg Andræ|Carl Andræ]] in [[Denmark]], where it was used briefly before being abandoned.{{Cn|date=July 2024}} It was later rediscovered by British lawyer [[Thomas Hare (political reformer)|Thomas Hare]], whose writings soon spread the method throughout the [[British Empire]]. [[Tasmania]] adopted the method in the 1890s, with broader adoption throughout [[Australia]] beginning in the 1910s and 1920s.<ref>Farrell and McAllister, The Australian Electoral System, p. 17</ref> It gained adoption in [[Ireland]], [[South Africa]], STV was adopted for governmental elections in Ireland, Malta, and approximately 20 cities each [[Ranked-choice voting in the United States|in the United States]] and [[Canada]].{{Cn|date=July 2024}}
The [[single transferable vote]] (STV) system was first invented by [[Carl Christoffer Georg Andræ|Carl Andræ]] in [[Denmark]], where it was used briefly before being abandoned.{{Cn|date=July 2024}} It was later rediscovered by British lawyer [[Thomas Hare (political reformer)|Thomas Hare]], whose writings soon spread the method throughout the [[British Empire]]. [[Tasmania]] adopted the method in the 1890s, with broader adoption throughout [[Australia]] beginning in the 1910s and 1920s.<ref>Farrell and McAllister, The Australian Electoral System, p. 17</ref> It has been adopted in [[Ireland]], [[South Africa]], [[Malta]], and approximately 20 cities each [[Ranked-choice voting in the United States|in the United States]] and [[Canada]].{{Cn|date=July 2024}}


In more recent years, STV has seen a comeback the United States. In November 2016, the voters of [[Maine]] narrowly passed Question 5, approving [[Instant-runoff voting|ranked-choice voting]] for all elections. This was first put to use in 2018, marking the inaugural use of a ranked choice voting system in a statewide election in the United States. Later, in November 2020, Alaska voters passed Measure 2, bringing ranked choice voting into effect from 2022.<ref>{{cite web |author=<!--Not stated--> |date=2022-08-23 |title=Ranked Choice Voting in Maine |url=https://www.legislature.maine.gov/lawlibrary/ranked-choice-voting-in-maine/9509 |access-date=2022-11-20 |website=legislature.maine.gov |publisher=State of Maine |quote=}}</ref><ref>{{cite web |last=Piper |first=Kelsey |date=2020-11-19 |title=Alaska voters adopt ranked-choice voting in ballot initiative |url=https://www.vox.com/2020/11/19/21537126/alaska-measure-2-ranked-choice-voting-results |access-date=2022-11-20 |website=vox.com |publisher=Vox Media |quote=}}</ref> However, as before, the system has faced strong opposition. After a series of [[Pathological (mathematics)|electoral pathologies]] in Alaska's [[2022 Alaska's at-large congressional district special election|2022 congressional special election]], a poll found 54% of Alaskans supported a repeal of the system; this included a third of the voters who had supported [[Mary Peltola|Peltola]], the ultimate winner in the election.<ref name="North">{{cite web |title=North to the Future: Alaska’s Ranked Choice Voting System is Praised and Criticized Nationally |url=https://alaskapublic.org/2023/09/19/north-to-the-future-alaskas-ranked-choice-voting-system-is-praised-and-criticized-nationally/ |publisher=Alaska Public Media}}</ref>
In more recent years, STV has seen a comeback the United States. In November 2016, the voters of [[Maine]] narrowly passed Question 5, approving [[Instant-runoff voting|ranked-choice voting]] for all elections. This was first put to use in 2018, marking the inaugural use of a ranked choice voting system in a statewide election in the United States. Later, in November 2020, Alaska voters passed Measure 2, bringing ranked choice voting into effect from 2022.<ref>{{cite web |author=<!--Not stated--> |date=2022-08-23 |title=Ranked Choice Voting in Maine |url=https://www.legislature.maine.gov/lawlibrary/ranked-choice-voting-in-maine/9509 |access-date=2022-11-20 |website=legislature.maine.gov |publisher=State of Maine |quote=}}</ref><ref>{{cite web |last=Piper |first=Kelsey |date=2020-11-19 |title=Alaska voters adopt ranked-choice voting in ballot initiative |url=https://www.vox.com/2020/11/19/21537126/alaska-measure-2-ranked-choice-voting-results |access-date=2022-11-20 |website=vox.com |publisher=Vox Media |quote=}}</ref> However, as before, the system has faced strong opposition. After a series of [[Pathological (mathematics)|electoral pathologies]] in Alaska's [[2022 Alaska's at-large congressional district special election|2022 congressional special election]], a poll found 54% of Alaskans supported a repeal of the system; this included a third of the voters who had supported [[Mary Peltola|Peltola]], the ultimate winner in the election.<ref name="North">{{cite web |title=North to the Future: Alaska’s Ranked Choice Voting System is Praised and Criticized Nationally |url=https://alaskapublic.org/2023/09/19/north-to-the-future-alaskas-ranked-choice-voting-system-is-praised-and-criticized-nationally/ |publisher=Alaska Public Media}}</ref>

Revision as of 16:03, 17 July 2024

Ovals
Names
Numbers
Various types of ranked voting ballot

The term ranked voting refers to any voting system that uses voters' orderings (rankings) of candidates to choose a single winner. For example, Dowdall's method assigns 1, 12, 13... points to the 1st, 2nd, 3rd... candidates on each ballot, then elects the candidate with the most points. Ranked voting systems vary dramatically in how preferences are tabulated and counted, which gives each one very different properties.

Ranked voting systems are usually contrasted with rated voting methods, which allow voters to indicate how strongly they support different candidates (e.g. on a scale from 0-10).[1] Rated voting systems use more information than ordinal ballots; as a result, they are not subject to many of the problems with ranked voting (including results like Arrow's theorem).[2][3][4]

Although not usually described as such, the most common ranked voting system is the well-known plurality rule, where each voter gives a single point to the candidate ranked first and zero points to all others. The most common non-degenerate ranked voting rule is the closely-related alternative vote, a staged variant of the plurality system that repeatedly eliminates last-place plurality winners.[5]

In the United States and Australia, the terms ranked-choice voting and preferential voting are usually used to refer to the alternative or single transferable vote by way of conflation. However, terms these have also been used to refer to ranked voting systems in general.

History of ranked voting

The earliest known proposals for a ranked voting system other than plurality can be traced to the works of Ramon Llull in the late 13th century, who developed what would later be known as Copeland's method. Copeland's method was devised by Ramon Llull in his 1299 treatise Ars Electionis, which was discussed by Nicholas of Cusa in the fifteenth century.[6][7]

A second wave of analysis began when Jean-Charles de Borda published a paper in 1781, advocating for the Borda count, which he called the "order of merit". This methodology drew criticism from the Marquis de Condorcet, who developed his own methods after arguing Borda's approach did not accurately reflect group preferences, because it was vulnerable to spoiler effects and did not always elect the majority-preferred candidate.[6]

Interest in ranked voting continued throughout the 19th century. Danish pioneer Carl Andræ formulated the single transferable vote (STV), which was adopted by his native Denmark in 1855. Condorcet had previously considered the single-winner version of it, the instant-runoff system, but immediately rejected it as pathological.[8][9]

Theoretical exploration of electoral processes was revived by a 1948 paper from Duncan Black[10] and Kenneth Arrow's investigations into social choice theory, a branch of welfare economics that extends rational choice to include community decision-making processes.[11]

Adoption

Plurality voting is the most common voting system, and has been in widespread use since the earliest democracies.[citation needed]

The single transferable vote (STV) system was first invented by Carl Andræ in Denmark, where it was used briefly before being abandoned.[citation needed] It was later rediscovered by British lawyer Thomas Hare, whose writings soon spread the method throughout the British Empire. Tasmania adopted the method in the 1890s, with broader adoption throughout Australia beginning in the 1910s and 1920s.[12] It has been adopted in Ireland, South Africa, Malta, and approximately 20 cities each in the United States and Canada.[citation needed]

In more recent years, STV has seen a comeback the United States. In November 2016, the voters of Maine narrowly passed Question 5, approving ranked-choice voting for all elections. This was first put to use in 2018, marking the inaugural use of a ranked choice voting system in a statewide election in the United States. Later, in November 2020, Alaska voters passed Measure 2, bringing ranked choice voting into effect from 2022.[13][14] However, as before, the system has faced strong opposition. After a series of electoral pathologies in Alaska's 2022 congressional special election, a poll found 54% of Alaskans supported a repeal of the system; this included a third of the voters who had supported Peltola, the ultimate winner in the election.[15]

In the United States, single-winner ranked voting is used to elect politicians in Maine[16] and Alaska.[17] Nauru uses a positional method called the Dowdall system. Some local elections in New Zealand use the single transferable vote.[18]

Theoretical foundations of ranked voting

Majority-rule

Many concepts formulated by the Marquis de Condorcet in the 18th century continue to significantly impact the field. One of these concepts is the Condorcet winner, the candidate preferred over all others by a majority of voters. A voting system that always elects this candidate is called a Condorcet method.

However, it is possible for an election to have no Condorcet winner, a situation called a Condorcet cycle: suppose an election with 3 candidates A, B, and C has 3 voters. One votes A–B–C, one votes B–C–A, and one votes B–C–A. In this case, no Condorcet winner exists: A cannot be a Condorcet winner as two-thirds of voters prefer B over A. Similarly, B cannot be the winner as two-thirds prefer C over B, and C cannot win as two-thirds prefer A over C. This forms a rock-paper-scissors style cycle with no Condorcet winner.

Social well-being

Voting systems can also be judged on their ability to deliver results that maximize the overall well-being of society, i.e. to choose the best candidate for society as a whole.[19]

Spatial voting models

Spatial voting models, initially proposed by Duncan Black and further developed by Anthony Downs, provide a theoretical framework for understanding electoral behavior. In these models, each voter and candidate is positioned within an ideological space that can span multiple dimensions. It is assumed that voters tend to favor candidates who closely align with their ideological position over those more distant. A political spectrum is an example of a one-dimensional spatial model.

A spatial model of voting

The accompanying diagram presents a simple one-dimensional spatial model, illustrating the voting methods discussed in subsequent sections of this article. It is assumed that supporters of candidate A cast their votes in the order of A-B-C, while candidate C's supporters vote in the sequence of C-B-A. Supporters of candidate B are equally divided between listing A or C as their second preference. From the data in the accompanying table, if there are 100 voters, the distribution of ballots will reflect the positioning of voters and candidates along the ideological spectrum.

Spatial models offer significant insights because they provide an intuitive visualization of voter preferences. These models give rise to an influential theorem—the median voter theorem—attributed to Duncan Black. This theorem stipulates that within a broad range of spatial models, including all one-dimensional models and all symmetric models across multiple dimensions, a Condorcet winner is guaranteed to exist. Moreover, this winner is the candidate closest to the median of the voter distribution.

Empirical research has generally found that spatial voting models give a highly accurate explanation of most voting behavior.[20]

Other theorems

Arrow's impossibility theorem is a generalization of Condorcet's result on the impossibility of majority rule. It demonstrates that every ranked voting algorithm is susceptible to the spoiler effect. Gibbard's theorem provides a closely-related corollary, that no voting rule can have a single, always-best strategy that does not depend on other voters' ballots.

Borda count

Candidate Score
A 87
B 130
C 83

The Borda count is a ranking system that assigns scores to each candidate based on their position in each ballot. If m is the total number of candidates, the candidate ranked first on a ballot receives m - 1 points, the second receives m - 2, and so on, until the last-ranked candidate who receives zero. In the given example, candidate B emerges as the winner with 130 out of a total 300 points.

While Borda count is simple to administer, it does not meet the Condorcet criterion. It has a significant limitation in that its result can be heavily influenced by the entry of candidates who themselves have no real possibility of winning.

Other positional systems

Systems that award points in a similar way but possibly with a different formula are called positional systems. The score vector (m - 1, m - 2,..., 0) is associated with the Borda count, (1, 1/2, 1/3,..., 1/m) defines the Dowdall system and (1, 0,... , 0) equates to first-past-the-post.

Instant-runoff voting

Candidate Count
1st round 2nd round 3rd round
A (votes marked A-B) 36 51 51
B (15 votes marked B-A; 15 marked B-C) 30 0 0
C (votes marked C-B) 34 49 49

Instant-runoff voting is a voting method that sequentially eliminates candidates in a series of rounds until a winner emerges. In this system, voters rank candidates in order of preference. If a candidate does not receive a majority of first-choice votes, the candidate with the fewest votes is eliminated, and their votes are redistributed according to the voters' next preferences. This process continues until one candidate receives a majority of the remaining votes.

In the given example, Candidate A is declared the winner in the second round, having received a majority of votes through the accumulation of first-choice votes and redistributed votes from Candidate B. This system embodies the voters' preferences between the final candidates, stopping when a candidate garners the preference of a majority of voters.

This method, unlike party-list proportional representation (PR), examines each transferred vote to respect the voter's ranking rather than allocating seats from a derived statistical table. Thus, it ensures a more accurate representation of voters' preferences.

IRV is notable in that it does not fulfill the Condorcet winner criterion, a property held by many other ranked voting systems. Furthermore, unlike its counterparts, IRV generally does not accommodate tied preferences, except occasionally among a voter's least preferred candidates. An adapted version of the single transferable vote (STV) system, intended for party ranking, was proposed for use in German elections in 2013.[21] This proposed system is referred to as the spare vote.[22]

Single transferable vote

An example of an STV election:

There are three positions to be elected, with a total of 100 votes. The quota, determined by the Droop method, is 26 votes.

Candidate Count
1st round 2nd round 3rd round 4th round
A (votes marked A-B) 26 (elected) Elected
B (votes marked B-E) 18 26 (elected) Elected
C (votes marked C-D) 17 17 17 (elected) Elected (as last remaining candidate to fill final seat)
D (votes marked D-C) 16 16 16 Eliminated
E (votes marked E-B) 15 15 Eliminated
F (votes marked F-B) 8 Eliminated

The Single transferable vote (STV) is a multi-winner method and a proportional version of IRV. Like IRV, STV allows for contingent voting based on secondary preferences, which only come into play if the first preference does not lead to an effective result. With STV, voters cast one vote with the possibility to mark back-up preferences. Initially, a voter's ballot is allocated to their most preferred candidate. After a candidate reaches the quota and is elected, surplus votes are transferred from this winner to remaining hopefuls based on the voter's preference order. If there are still vacant seats, the least performing candidates are eliminated, and their votes are transferred to the remaining contenders. Different versions of STV might use varying methodologies for eliminating candidates and transferring votes.

Minimax

Candidate preference comparison Second candidate
A B C
First candidate A 36:64 51:49
B 64:36 66:34
C 49:51 34:66

The Minimax voting system determines the winner by constructing a comparison table of candidate preferences, as shown above. This table illustrates the preferences between each pair of distinct candidates (A, B, C). The cell value x:y represents that x voters prefer the first candidate over the second, while y voters have the opposite preference. This data is derived from the ranked votes provided in the Spatial Model section above.

Each row identifies the least satisfactory outcome (i.e., minimal preference) for the first candidate, highlighted in bold. The winning candidate is the one whose least satisfactory outcome is most favorable.

In this specific example, candidate B is the winner. Despite B's worst performance being a 64:36 victory margin over candidate A, this is the most favorable least satisfactory result when compared to those of the other candidates.

The Minimax method, which is straightforward in determining the winner from a set of ballots, satisfies the Condorcet criterion. It elects the Condorcet winner, if one exists. Otherwise, it selects the candidate who comes closest to being a Condorcet winner under a simple metric.

Llull's method and Copeland's method

Candidate Score
A 1
B 2
C 0

Copeland's method assigns a score to each candidate derived from the results table, as shown above in the minimax section. The score is simply the number of favourable results in a candidate's row, i.e., the number of other candidates to whom a specific candidate is preferred by a majority of voters. The candidate with the highest score (in this case B) is the winner.

Copeland's method is Condorcet-consistent and straightforward, but for certain patterns of voter preferences (with no Condorcet winner), it will yield a tie regardless of the size of the electorate. Therefore, its proponents typically recommend its use in conjunction with a tie-breaker. Suitable rules for this purpose include minimax, IRV, and the Borda count, the latter giving rise to the Dasgupta–Maskin method.

Other methods

Several other voting methods provide alternatives to the methods described above, each with unique characteristics:

  • Ranked voting: Different from cardinal voting, candidates are independently rated rather than ranked.[23]
  • Condorcet completions: Elects the Condorcet winner if there is one and otherwise falls back on a separate procedure for determining the result. Examples include Black's method when using the Borda count as the fallback and the Nicolaus Tideman Condorcet-Hare when using IRV.[24]
  • Bottom-two-runoff IRV or BTR-IRV: A Condorcet-consistent variant of IRV.
  • Coombs' method: A variant of IRV where the candidate eliminated in each round has the most last-place preferences rather than the fewest first-place choices. Not Condorcet-consistent but satisfies the median voter theorem.[25]
  • Smith's method: Reduces the set of candidates to the Smith set, which contains the Condorcet winner if there is one. Advocated for use with a tie-break, like IRV and minimax.[26]
  • Bucklin's method: Exists in several forms, some of which are Condorcet-consistent.
  • Expanding approvals rule

See also

References

  1. ^ Riker, William Harrison (1982). Liberalism against populism: a confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. Waveland Pr. pp. 29–30. ISBN 0881333670. OCLC 316034736. Ordinal utility is a measure of preferences in terms of rank orders—that is, first, second, etc. ... Cardinal utility is a measure of preferences on a scale of cardinal numbers, such as the scale from zero to one or the scale from one to ten.
  2. ^ Hamlin, Aaron (2012-10-06). "Podcast 2012-10-06: Interview with Nobel Laureate Dr. Kenneth Arrow". The Center for Election Science. Archived from the original on 2023-06-05.

    Dr. Arrow: Well, I’m a little inclined to think that score systems where you categorize in maybe three or four classes probably (in spite of what I said about manipulation) is probably the best.

  3. ^ Hamlin, Aaron (2012-10-06). "Podcast 2012-10-06: Interview with Nobel Laureate Dr. Kenneth Arrow". The Center for Election Science. Archived from the original on 2023-06-05.

    Dr. Arrow: Well, I’m a little inclined to think that score systems where you categorize in maybe three or four classes (in spite of what I said about manipulation) is probably the best.[...] And some of these studies have been made. In France, [Michel] Balinski has done some studies of this kind which seem to give some support to these scoring methods.

  4. ^ Hamlin, Aaron (2012-10-06). "Podcast 2012-10-06: Interview with Nobel Laureate Dr. Kenneth Arrow". The Center for Election Science. Archived from the original on 2023-06-05.
    CES: Now, you mention that your theorem applies to preferential systems or ranking systems.
    Dr. Arrow: Yes.
    CES: But the system that you're just referring to, approval voting, falls within a class called cardinal systems. So not within ranking systems.
    Dr. Arrow: And as I said, that in effect implies more information.
  5. ^ "Bill Status H.424: An act relating to town, city, and village elections for single-seat offices using ranked-choice voting". legislature.vermont.gov. Retrieved 2024-03-23. Condorcet winner. If a candidate is the winning candidate in every paired comparison, the candidate shall be declared the winner of the election.
  6. ^ a b George G. Szpiro, "Numbers Rule: The Vexing Mathematics of Democracy, from Plato to the Present" (2010).
  7. ^ Colomer, Josep M. (2013-02-01). "Ramon Llull: from 'Ars electionis' to social choice theory". Social Choice and Welfare. 40 (2): 317–328. doi:10.1007/s00355-011-0598-2. ISSN 1432-217X.
  8. ^ Nanson, E. J. (1882). "Methods of election: Ware's Method". Transactions and Proceedings of the Royal Society of Victoria. 19: 206. The method was, however, mentioned by Condorcet, but only to be condemned.
  9. ^ Condorcet, Jean-Antoine-Nicolas de Caritat (1788). "On the Constitution and the Functions of Provincial Assemblies". Complete Works of Condorcet (in French). Vol. 13 (published 1804). p. 243. En effet, lorsqu'il y a plus de trois concurrents, le véritable vœu de la pluralité peut être pour un candidat qui n'ait eu aucune des voix dans le premier scrutin.
  10. ^ Duncan Black, "On the Rationale of Group Decision-making" (1948).
  11. ^ Arrow, Kenneth Joseph Arrow (1963). Social Choice and Individual Values (PDF). Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0300013641. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  12. ^ Farrell and McAllister, The Australian Electoral System, p. 17
  13. ^ "Ranked Choice Voting in Maine". legislature.maine.gov. State of Maine. 2022-08-23. Retrieved 2022-11-20.
  14. ^ Piper, Kelsey (2020-11-19). "Alaska voters adopt ranked-choice voting in ballot initiative". vox.com. Vox Media. Retrieved 2022-11-20.
  15. ^ "North to the Future: Alaska's Ranked Choice Voting System is Praised and Criticized Nationally". Alaska Public Media.
  16. ^ "Ranked Choice Voting in Maine". Maine State Legislature. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
  17. ^ "Alaska Better Elections Implementation". Alaska Division of Elections. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
  18. ^ "New Zealand Cities Voting to Implement Ranked Choice Voting". 19 September 2017.
  19. ^ Weber, Robert J. (September 1978). "Comparison of Public Choice Systems". Cowles Foundation Discussion Papers. Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics: 16, 38, 62. No. 498.
  20. ^ T. N. Tideman and F. Plassman, "Modeling the Outcomes of Vote-Casting in Actual Elections" (2012).
  21. ^ Alternative II.: Einführung einer Ersatzstimme (in German)
  22. ^ What is Dual Level Voting?
  23. ^ Riker, William Harrison (1982). Liberalism against populism: a confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. Waveland Pr. pp. 29–30. ISBN 0881333670. OCLC 316034736. Ordinal utility is a measure of preferences in terms of rank orders—that is, first, second, etc. ... Cardinal utility is a measure of preferences on a scale of cardinal numbers, such as the scale from zero to one or the scale from one to ten.
  24. ^ J. Green-Armytage, T. N. Tideman and R. Cosman, "Statistical Evaluation of Voting Rules" (2015).
  25. ^ B. Grofman and S. L. Feld, "If you like the alternative vote (a.k.a. the instant runoff), then you ought to know about the Coombs rule" (2004)
  26. ^ R. B. Darlington, "Are Condorcet and Minimax Voting Systems the Best?" (v8, 2021).
  27. ^ W. H. Holliday and E. Pacuit, "Split Cycle: A New Condorcet Consistent Voting Method Independent of Clones and Immune to Spoilers" (2021).