Skip to main content

HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY article

Front. Psychol., 10 July 2024
Sec. Consciousness Research

Documenting and defining emergent phenomenology: theoretical foundations for an extensive research strategy

  • 1Emergence Benefactors, Huntsville, AL, United States
  • 2Emergent Phenomenology Research Consortium, New Market, AL, United States

Meditation, psychedelics, and other similar practices or induction methods that can modulate conscious experience, are becoming increasingly popular in clinical and non-clinical settings. The phenomenology associated with such practices or modalities is vast. Many similar effects and experiences are also reported to occur spontaneously. We argue that this experiential range is still not fully described or understood in the contemporary literature, and that there is an ethical mandate to research it more extensively, starting with comprehensive documentation and definition. We review 50 recent clinical or scientific publications to assess the range of phenomena, experiences, effects, after-effects, and impacts associated with a broad variety of psychoactive compounds, meditative practices, and other modalities or events. This results in a large inventory synthesizing the reports of over 30,000 individual subjects. We then critically discuss various terms and concepts that have been used in recent literature to designate all or parts of the range this inventory covers. We make the case that specialized terminologies are needed to ground the nascent research field that is forming around this experiential domain. As a step in this direction, we propose the notion of “emergence” and some of its derivatives, such as “emergent phenomenology,” as possibly foundational candidates.

1 Introduction

1.1 Background

Cross-cultural anthropologists tell us that there are “upwards of 4,000 known societies, approximately 90% of which have one or more institutionalized forms of Altered-State of Consciousness induction” (Bourguignon, 1973; Locke and Kelly, 1985). This represents a substantial portion of the global population and of cultures. Yet, these “altered states” (ASCs henceforth) are not well-understood despite their centrality to many cultures, religions, and philosophical systems. They are often pathologized in both traditional and mainstream clinical contexts. Although there are issues with the notion of ASCs, which will be discussed below, this salient fact will serve as a platform on which to ground the present discussion.

On the more challenging and thus clinically-relevant end of the experiential spectrum, some extreme presentations can resemble what, according to current mainstream clinical practice, are mental disorders or episodes. The overlap, equivalence, and separation of these is still unclear.

This is why, in 1993, the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual (DSM) added criteria to exempt those from a diagnosis of mental illness who were experiencing hallucinations, delusions, or other unusual experiences that were expected in their spiritual tradition who also maintained sufficient function and did not meet other criteria for mental illness.1

Examining the text of the most recent edition of the DSM (DSM-5-TR, American Psychiatric Association, 2022) itself, we find there is simultaneously a profound upgrade from what came in the DSM-IV and before, but also a significant lack in the degree of depth and detail that the added material presupposes should be available to clinicians either in their clinical education, life experience, or in further supplementary references.

The DSM-5-TR provides few characterizations of the religious, spiritual or culturally-sanctioned experiences which call for modifier labels and may be collectively referred to here as “spiritual exemption criteria.” These are limited and hard to apply, reflecting a lack of awareness of the norms of the various religious or spiritual traditions, but also a lack of research into the experiences themselves, and/or a lack of integration of existing findings into mainstream contexts.

What to define as “hallucinations” and “delusions” is clearly culturally determined, as histories of the topic reveal (e.g., Spittles, 2022). Hence such definitions and the risks, benefits, and alternatives to their adoption require careful consideration. Moreover, the Z65.8 diagnostic code “Religious or spiritual problem,” is framed largely in terms of questions of faith and culture rather than other sorts of experiences.2

Other guidebooks on religious or spiritual experiences for healthcare providers do not, to our knowledge, offer a comprehensive presentation of the full range of phenomena and experiences of interest here, nor of the practices or triggers which can lead to these manifestations. Instead, they also mostly focus on other aspects of spiritual or religious life that may be relevant in a therapeutic setting. For instance, the World Psychiatry Association’s Position Statement on Spirituality and Religion in Psychiatry (Moreira-Almeida et al., 2016) proposes that religion and spirituality should play a more important role in psychiatric practice, but its guidelines are quite general, although the second proposition states: “An understanding of religion and spirituality and their relationship to the diagnosis, etiology and treatment of psychiatric disorders should be considered as essential components of both psychiatric training and continuing professional development.”

Similarly, the World Health Organization, Quality of Life Spirituality, Religion and Personal Beliefs Group (2006) has recognized the importance of religion and spirituality on quality of life but does not provide much documentation on the phenomenology nor theory of these experiences. This is also true of major medical textbooks such as Tintinalli et al. (2020) or Rosen’s/Walls et al. (2022) (for emergency medicine). Other works about spiritual competency in clinical contexts tend to propose very general skillsets and often do not much discuss the details of the experiences in question nor ways to manage difficult variants nor cultivate desirable ones — see, e.g., Vieten and Scammell (2015).

In sum, although major international resources like the latest International Classification of Diseases (ICD-11, World Health Organization, 2019) and the DSM-5-TR contain diagnostic/billing codes for “Spiritual or Religious Problems,” there is, to our knowledge, no definitive resource on the experiences and phenomena which the various religions, spiritual traditions, and cultural contexts consider as normal, expected, desirable, or pathological. Yet, without such a resource, how could healthcare workers be expected to adequately respond to the challenging variants of these phenomena, and correctly differentiate them from pathology?

A large and growing body of anecdotal evidence clearly shows that these experiences are not limited to specific cultural, religious, or spiritual circumstances or institutions, but are reported to occur:

(1) Within cultural, institutional or practice contexts that do not have concepts or frameworks to recognize or explain them (Lindahl et al., 2017, 2020, 2022a,b). Crucially, the lack of a normative framework, or conflict between unexpected or novel experiences and one’s worldviews or expectations, are often associated with increased difficulty processing or integrating them (Bitbol, 2014; Lindahl et al., 2022a,b);

(2) Outside of any established tradition, either as:

a. Intentionally cultivated through various individual and group-level modalities and practices conducive to such experiences, perceptions, or personal changes. The variety of such activities is immense, including but not limited to specific types of internal gestures as in prayer, hypnosis, meditation and contemplation (Grabovac, 2014; Schlosser et al., 2019; Sparby and Sacchet, 2022; Galante et al., 2023), psychoactive substances (Breeksema and van Elk, 2021; Timmermann et al., 2022), movement (Piarulli et al., 2018), breathing exercises, rhythmic music (TaKeTiNa, drumming), chanting, sensory deprivation, electrical stimulation (Piarulli et al., 2018), and more. Many of these are becoming increasingly popular in clinical settings [e.g., mindfulness-based intervention or psychedelic-assisted therapy (Mitchell et al., 2023)] and in secularized and cross-cultural religious or spiritual contexts, or

b. As unintended side effects of engaging in such practices (Lindahl et al., 2017). As quoted in Galante et al. (2023): “Increasing evidence shows a wide range of experiences that can arise with regular mindfulness meditation, from profoundly positive to challenging and potentially harmful”;

(3) Unintentionally or seemingly “spontaneously” — emerging from a convergence of causes that we do not currently understand — with various sociocultural, personal, and contextual factors probably playing an important role (Locke and Kelly, 1985; Miller and C'de Baca, 2001; Lindahl et al., 2022b; Timmermann et al., 2022; Yaden and Newberg, 2022). A broad range of such triggers is reported in various literatures, e.g., nature, stress, childbirth, grief, trauma, loss, diet, sleep deprivation, sexual relations, aesthetic and artistic experiences, and more (Sartre, 1957; Locke and Kelly, 1985; Lapassade, 1987; Fink, 1995; James, 2005; Hulin, 2008; Sandilands, 2019; Corneille and Luke, 2021; Yaden and Newberg, 2022).

On the other end of the spectrum, modern research and many religions or spiritual traditions claim remarkable benefits can be achieved through various cultivation methods (James, 2005), beyond what is usually envisioned in most recent research, which often focuses on relaxation, efficiency, stress-reduction, alleviating depression, coping with pain, etc. Although it is important to distinguish between ideals and achievable human goals, this also warrants further investigation.

1.2 An ethical mandate

The high prevalence in most times and places of the experiences in question demonstrates their enduring importance for humans. This stands in stark contrast with the paucity of information on these which is available to the public in many mainstream contexts, including contemporary healthcare systems.

Researchers have been calling for a dramatic increase in the scope of phenomena that should be carefully considered, as well as in the systematicity, multidisciplinarity, quality, variety, and long-term coordination of research endeavors (Sparby, 2017; Van Dam et al., 2018; Vieten et al., 2018; Galante et al., 2023).

From a medical ethics perspective, as we will detail in a forthcoming article, it is clear there is a mandate to:

• Fill that knowledge gap so as to avoid harming patients presenting with challenging emergent phenomena because of ignorance (thereby respecting the ethical principle of Nonmaleficence);

• Promote beneficial effects by exploring the remarkable claims of positive outcomes made by countless secular, religious, or spiritual traditions which cultivate the positive side of these experiences (Beneficence);

• Provide information on risks, benefits, and alternatives in clinical but also in all non-medical contexts that promote activities which may lead to the experiences in question (Autonomy);

• And abide by the principle of Justice3 by distributing benefits and burdens equitably.

It follows that thoroughgoing research into this domain, as well as strategies to integrate important findings in the various contexts we outlined, should be developed. In this context, we advocate for the principles of: (1) ontological neutrality — suspending ontological judgments and instead focusing on phenomenology and clinical pragmatism —, (2) neutrality and global scalability regarding terminological and conceptual choices, (3) high epistemological and methodological rigor for fundamental qualitative and empirical research, and (4) the pragmatic goal of improving human flourishing and reducing suffering.

1.3 Aims and method

Given the complexity of the causal processes likely involved, we believe much work is still needed to elucidate these types of experiences and phenomena. We also believe that before solid empirical evidence can be obtained, much descriptive, definitional, conceptual, and review work are required. Indeed, all the current or past research projects we are aware of suffer from various limitations on these fronts.4

To help those dealing with the particular categories of experiences and effects which are delineated at length, in an open-ended but still very specific and detailed way, in section 2 below, the creation of a new board-certified clinical specialty may be required.

To do so, one must first define a body of knowledge that the specialty covers which has not been adequately covered by the scopes of previous boards and has demonstrable clinical relevance. The present article aims to formally begin that process, and proposes a functional, clinical, pragmatic approach that may lead to the definition of a specialty, and at the very least will help advance our understanding of this domain.

Such a program should be founded on what is often regarded as the fundamental stepping stone of any scientific endeavor — description and definition (Hoyningen-Huene, 2013; Sparby, 2017). This in turn requires extensive documentation, the development of dedicated terminologies, and contemporary data-driven taxonomies.

The present contribution starts with description, inventorying a selection of 50 recent scientific publications which document phenomena, experiences, after-effects, and impacts in the short to long term associated with various modalities of intentional cultivation, including various psychedelic compounds, meditative and contemplative practices, and therapies explicitly based on such meditative/contemplative techniques or psychedelics, for example clinical applications of mindfulness, as well as similar experiences and effects that occurred outside of those contexts and sometimes without an obvious cause.

We then critically discuss various concepts and terms used in recent research to reference the general domain delineated in the first part of this article.

Finally, based on the observation that, as has been the case for most new fields of knowledge in modern history, professional lexicons with specialized terminologies need to be developed, we introduce the notions of “emergence,” “emergent phenomena,” and related concepts, and discuss their merits, limitations, and relation with other common words such as ASCs, religion, spirituality, and mysticism.

The present article is meant to pave the way to long-term, coordinated, high-quality experimental research, but is not an empirical paper. Rather, it proposes a novel synthesis of existing qualitative data, followed by extensive analytical discussion meant to provide clarification in this notably elusive domain. Its core proposals are descriptive and definitional.

Note that our goal is not to impose our own preferred views, methods, and/or terms, but rather to help expand and move the field forward by integrating clinical, scientific, and spiritual paradigms. We hope that fruitful debates will follow and lead to much needed normalization.

2 Documenting the range of phenomena, experiences, effects, and after-effects of interest

2.1 Methodology

To help define our domain of interest and document its broad scope, we decided to survey recent scientific publications from our field. To that end, we selected 38 clinical, psychiatric, or qualitative publications on meditation, 37 on psychedelics, and 21 for other induction methods or “spontaneous” experiences, striving to include a diversity of modalities, study-designs, and thematic foci to make sure our sample would provide an accurate picture of this experiential landscape. Because the extant literature has various limitations and is too large to comprehensively review, we have opted for an open-ended approach, manually selecting higher-quality than average publications, rather than conducting a keyword search on selected databases, e.g., following the Preferred Reporting Items for Systematic reviews and Meta-Analyses (PRISMA) guidelines (Page et al., 2021). We did not formally assess the quality of each paper for similar reasons.

Indeed, as discussed at length in Supplementary file S2, we acknowledge that most of these studies have limitations in terms of rigor or precision, including:

• A lack phenomenological and/or meditative expertise of subjects and/or researchers;

• The use of sometimes crude tools, particularly in the case of clinical trials with low-quality scales for outcome measures;

• Uncertain causal attribution;

• Biased interpretations or appraisals;

• Evaluations or appraisals which do not take into account the sometimes non-linear development of some of these phenomena (Fisher, 2019), etc.

We thus excluded publications which (1) did not contain new qualitative information, for instance articles that mostly focused on physiological correlates or on philosophical considerations, by reviewing the methods sections and excluding articles which did not employ first-person methods, (2) only used pre-existing structured questionnaires, since these provide information about prevalence and correlation of specific factors, but no additional phenomenology, or (3) were too specific [e.g., a micro phenomenological study of the experience of mind-wandering during meditation (Petitmengin et al., 2017)].This elicited a corpus of 23, 22, and 15 publications for each of the three groups, respectively.

We then reviewed, extracted and recategorized the qualitative reports of phenomena, experiences, and after-effects and impacts associated with these various modalities in the immediate, short-, mid- and long-terms into a large and synchronic thematic framework that covers a wide variety of functional and experiential dimensions.

Our data-analysis was based on the micro-phenomenological method (Petitmengin, 2006; Petitmengin et al., 2017, 2019). New labels were added to the categorizations found within the publications when the qualitative data seemed to require it. The analytical scheme was frontloaded by synthesizing several theoretical frameworks of a descriptive or functional nature borrowed from classical phenomenology, recent qualitative publications, and biomedical research [e.g., the Research Domain Criteria (Cuthbert and Insel, 2013)], as detailed in Supplementary file S1.

Given our focus, we excluded all non-phenomenological information that could not be generalized to the whole sample, such as demographics, context, intensity, severity, duration, appraisal, prevalence.

Once we approached a form of categorial saturation, meaning analyzing new articles did not seem to add new themes to our inventory, we stopped, ending up with a total of 50 articles. The titles and types of these publications are listed in Supplementary file S2, in a table which also contains information on modality, substance, or precipitating context, and number of participants.

2.2 Results

Our main result is a fine-meshed functional and descriptive inventory of experiences, effects, after-effects, and impacts associated with various induction modalities and contexts, representing the aggregated experiences of 30,100 individual subjects, thus covering a vaster phenomenological range than any research initiative we are aware of.

Since the data we synthesized is substantial and would far exceed length requirements, what follows is a short table listing the types of emergent experiences and effects we identified, along with their subdimensions, illustrated by a single sample item. Nota bene: in cases where a given category has several subdimensions, we only include 1 or 2 sample items for the general category, rather than giving a sample for each sub- or sub-subcategory (Table 1).

Table 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. Variety of emergent phenomena, experiences, and effects with sample item.

The full inventory can be found in Supplementary file S2. It contains a full list of reviewed publications with relevant accompanying information, commentary on the quality of reviewed research, discussion of the phenomenological and/or meditative expertise of researchers and subjects, appraisals, etiology, and further breakdown of our methodological choices.

We strongly advise that the reader consult this file, as it is much larger than the table included in the present section, and because, despite some degree of overlap between the categories it is divided into, this extensive list will help define the domain we are interested in, thus grounding the terminological and conceptual considerations which follow.

3 Discussion

3.1 Defining our domain

Although it should be seen as the first iteration of an open and expansive collection which will be refined and upgraded, the Supplementary file S2 inventory conveys in both broad and very specific terms what we mean by this field we are working to help define, although the latter is not limited to the contents of this inventory.

It must be noted that the phenomena and effects we are interested in, including but not limited to those found in Supplementary file S2, are not modality specific, as there is considerable overlap across induction-methods. What is outlined here seems to be a specific domain of experience and perhaps development that cannot be adequately broken-up on the sole basis of practice-type or context of occurrence. This hypothesis is supported by existing literature, although the latter is currently somewhat scattered throughout traditions and disciplines.

Overall, and as alluded to in our introduction, what many call Altered-States of Consciousness (ASCs) comes closest to the domain we are trying to define here. The notion does convey the intuitive unity of the experiential and practical domain of concern, and recent initiatives such as the Altered-States Database (Schmidt and Berkemeyer, 2018; Prugger et al., 2022) align with our core hypothesis — namely, that the dedicated study of this domain across induction methods and contexts of occurrence is possible and desirable.

However, major issues with the static and vague term of ASCs, detailed in section 3.5.1 below, lead us to the firm conclusion that another name is required.

Crucially, we feel that approaches which rely exclusively on existing psychometric scales do not adequately cover the range of experiences and effects of interest, as these instruments often suffer from limited synchronic and diachronic precision (i.e., macro and micro-phenomenological details of the character and/or temporal unfolding of the “states” being studied), often use ambiguous or vague terms and wordings, and rely on pre-interpretations, theories, and sometimes arbitrary or logically inconsistent statements, to the point that it is sometimes virtually impossible to know what experience a person is actually reporting when responding through a Likert grade. We unpack these specific issues in section 3.5 below.

As discussed in the introductory remarks of inventory Supplementary file S2, these pitfalls are specifically what first-person methods like micro-phenomenology (which we used in our re-analysis) are designed to avoid.

Even though standard statistical tools may find good psychometric properties for such scales, we believe this does not fully compensate for the issues caused by a problematically vague initial description of the phenomena in question — which is one of the core reasons why we believe that better and more extensive description and improved definition of terms are needed.

We believe these various limitations in prevalent concepts and scales, a lack of precision which can usually be extended to the description of induction methods, risk hindering outcomes research (Lundh, 2022; Sparby and Sacchet, 2022). This may have negative downstream implications on the reliability, validity, and replicability of the research that will be informed by it — possibly at the eventual detriment of practitioners and patients.

One of the ambitions of the present inventory is the development of structured questionnaires that are more precise, extensive, and less ambiguous than existing instruments, to then launch large-scale empirical studies employing an array of methods, such as micro-phenomenological interviews, and structured questionnaires based on further iterations of the present inventory.

Now that we have defined our domain by providing extensive, though preliminary documentation, we turn to definition, and critically discuss some of the most common terms used in recent research to designate our domain.

3.2 Discussing existing terms

It must be said that many secular and religions or spiritual traditions possess their own vernaculars for experiences and effects that seem to fall within our domain. A few examples are:

1. Conversion, Dark night of the soul, Unio mystica,5 Contemplation, Theoria,6 Theosis,7 Nepsis,8 Glorification9 [Christianity — see, e.g., James (2005), Depraz (2008), St. John of the Cross (2010), and Rose (2016)]

2. Hal,10 Maqām,11 Qabd,12 Fanā’,13 Wajd,14 Junun15 [Islam — see Fisher (2022)]

3. Samādhi,16 Chakras,17 Moksha18 [Hinduism — see, e.g., Rose (2016)]

4. Jhānas,19 Siddhis,20 Nirodha, Nirodha Samāpatti21 [Buddhism – see, e.g., Sayadaw (1994), Rose (2016), Sparby (2019), and Laukkonen et al. (2023)]

5. Hitbodedut,22 Tardama,23 Halom, Hazon, Ayin,24 Bittul25 [Judaism — see, e.g., Fisher (2022)].

6. Metanoia,26 Henosis27 [Ancient Greece and Neoplatonism — see Mazur et al. (2021) and Hadot (2002)]

Such notions often have specific canonical characteristics, usually described as gestalts,28 which could be seen as combinations of the more granular categories in Supplementary file S2 and analyzed in the same way. For instance, in canonical Buddhist texts, states of jhāna are often described through a five- or sixfold dimensional matrix of interrelated and covariant volitional, cognitive-attentional, affective and sensate factors.29 Different states of jhāna [8 or 9 are distinguished — see, e.g., Laukkonen et al. (2023)] have different “signatures” of relative salience of these various components. This is quite similar to the approach advocated for by Vion-Dury and Mougin (2016) — i.e. to characterize various “states” as specific modalizations, specific combinations of basic phenomenal dimensions.

However, we will not attempt such an analysis in the present paper, though it will be the subject of a later article. Importantly, traditional systems usually fit these into developmental and etiological theories. These should also be reviewed, although we cannot do this here.

Our focus will rather be the wide variety of analogous terms and typologies which have been used in recent scientific research. Among these there are larger “umbrella” terms, and a plethora of specific experience-types and variants. These are usually differentiated based on their content, structure, context, or the modality or hypothetical cause that induced them.

Broader, collective terms include spiritual experiences (e.g., Yaden and Newberg, 2022); religious experiences (James, 2005); spiritual emergence/emergency (Grof and Grof, 1989; Louchakova, 2006); spiritually transformative experiences (Kason, 2019; Brook, 2021); and altered-states of consciousness or ASCs (Tart, 1969; Lapassade, 1987), among others. We will discuss these in section 3.5.

For now we will focus on narrower, individual types and names including: contemplative and meditative experiences (Lindahl et al., 2017); psychedelic experiences; mystical experiences (Stace, 1987; James, 2005; Streib et al., 2020); mystical experience with psychotic features (Lukoff et al., 1995); transpersonal experiences (Grof and Grof, 1989); archetypal experiences (Jung, 1980; Hillman, 2004); peak-, nadir- and plateau-experiences (Maslow, 2014); self-actualization (Maslow, 1943); spontaneous spiritual awakenings and spontaneous kundalini awakening (Corneille and Luke, 2021); energy-like somatic experiences (Cooper et al., 2021); kundalini experiences (Woollacott et al., 2021) or kundalini syndrome (Benning et al., 2019); extraordinary or anomalous experiences (Vieten et al., 2018); non-ordinary states of consciousness (Aixalà, 2022); psychic phenomena and extrasensory perceptions (Aixalà, 2022); unusual abilities (Locke and Kelly, 1985); near-death experiences (Greyson and Stevenson, 1980; Jung, 1989; Charland-Verville et al., 2014; Martial et al., 2019); out-of-body experiences (Bünning and Blanke, 2005; Mudgal et al., 2021); transcendent states or transcendental experiences (Wahbeh et al., 2018); self-transcendent states (Hanley et al., 2020); quantum change (Miller and C'de Baca, 2001). These often branch out into further sub- or sub-subtypes which we will not go into to remain in scope.

From our perspective, which looks at the experiences and effects documented in the inventory (Supplementary file S2) as a single experiential group, and from a pragmatic, phenomenological, ontologically agnostic, outcomes focused, therapeutic perspective, these terms share various problems, as they are:

(1) Excessively specific — many do not convey the general perspective we are adopting. This is not to say that there aren’t common, intuitive types30of phenomena such as mystical or archetypal, as we do use such labels in our inventory. Rather, that our own interests here include many labels since we look at the full range of effects, even those which would probably not be seen as mystical or archetypal by most. Regarding, e.g., “spiritually transformative experiences,” and “self-actualization”: clearly, not all the experiences we are concerned with here are necessarily reported to be “transformative” or “actualizing.”

(2) Metaphysically bound and/or Interpretative rather than descriptive. “Kundalini,” “extrasensory perceptions,” “psychic phenomena,” “transpersonal,” “transcendent,” “transcendental,” etc., all imply various degrees of speculation about the ontological nature of an experience, its etiology, or its epistemology. As a single example, transpersonal experiences are so named because they are interpreted as the surfacing of memories belonging to a hypothetical psychological dimension which Jung called the “collective unconscious.” The notion thus implies a combination of metaphysical and etiological assumptions which could be debated.

(3) Modality-bound, when in practice, there is considerable overlap across modalities in terms of phenomenology.

(4) Culturally-bound and/or Idiosyncratic, e.g., “nadir experience,” “Kundalini,” “awakening,” “Spontaneous spiritual awakening,” “quantum change.” These words possess specific histories, coming from specific traditions (e.g., “awakening” likely comes from translations of Buddhism), where they often possess a range of complex, highly technical, and sometimes contradictory definitions and criteria that vary by denomination and individual teachers and interpreters.

(5) Syncretic, e.g., “Kundalini Syndrome,” “quantum change.”

(6) Not representative of the widespread prevalence of such experiences and effects in most cultures in most times and place, as implied by adjectives like “unusual” or “extraordinary.”

(7) Pathologizing, or otherwise excessively normative, e.g., “anomalous” or “altered.”

(8) Imprecise, descriptively, linguistically, historically, or philosophically, e.g.:

(a) “Transcendental” has several meanings:

(i) It may carry a connotation of grandiosity or majesty (such as the Transcendental Études by romantic composer and virtuoso Franz Liszt);

(ii) It may relate to specific meditation techniques (such as Transcendental meditation);

(iii) It may be used technically: Kantian transcendental philosophy is not about specifically “transcendental” experiences or states (an oxymoron), but about the conditions of possibilities and limits of experience (“transcendental aesthetics”) and knowledge (“transcendental logic”). As quoted in the Critique of Pure Reason (Kant, 2007): “I call all knowledge transcendental if it is occupied, not with objects, but with the way that we can possibly know objects even before we experience them.” This has limited overlap with what we are talking about here, and instead was a very influential philosophical innovation, partly a reaction to British empiricism, which shaped the history of post-Kantian thinking, and directly influenced the birth of classical phenomenology — which Husserl called a form of “transcendental philosophy” (Husserl, 1970; Fink, 1995) —, and in recent developments in the philosophy of science (De la Tremblaye and Bitbol, 2022);

(iv) There is such a thing as transcendental mind states in Husserl’s philosophy, and these are linked with accomplishing the épochè and the “transcendental reduction” (Bitbol, 2019; Blouin, 2022). But the meaning of these terms is controversial (Barber, 2021; Stone and Zahavi, 2021), and it is doubtful that, even if we managed to agree on the fact that the post-épochè transcendental reduction leads to one or several specific “states” of mind, that these would resemble those induced by, for example, Transcendental Meditation, which are quite varied and would hardly all fit under the label “transcendental experience” (Castillo, 1990);

(v) Furthermore, the term transcendental is often confused with the word “transcendent” but is quite different.

(b) Expressions using this latter term, such as Transcendence/Transcendent states/Self-transcendent experiences, also have many possible meanings, implications, and uses:

(i) While the term sometimes carries “esoteric” connotations, logically speaking, a “transcendent experience” makes little sense, since what is transcendent is in fact “beyond experience,” transcending what we presently experience (which is immanent): how could we experience what is beyond experience? Yet this is precisely the implication of the notion of a “transcendent state.” This point is made by some Abrahamic mystical theologians, when they talk about the unknowability of a transcendent or hidden god, deus in absconditus, as in church father pseudo-Dionysius’ Mystical Theology (Pseudo-Dionysius, 1987).

(ii) A more subtle critique is that “transcendence” is not only characteristic of specific experience types, since it is in some ways inherent to our “natural attitude” (in the Husserlian sense) when relating with the objects and subjects which populate our world. This is a fundamental point made by classical or theoretical phenomenologists (Husserl, 1970; Henry, 2008) and various other philosophical schools (e.g., Madhyamaka). Philosophically speaking, whenever one adopts a realistic worldview that posits the existence of a stable entity in or behind ordinary mundane phenomena, there is transcendence — because we usually neither reduce “objects” nor other “subjects” to the present incomplete perception we have of them. As quoted in De La Tremblaye and Bitbol (2022): “Any intentional aiming of an object … intends infinitely more than what is intuitively given. (The object) is a Kantian teleological idea (Pradelle, 2008). This ‘infinitely more’ which the expectations of a present consciousness imply, is precisely what we mean when we claim that an object ‘transcends’ consciousness.” Thus, how could this adequately differentiate specific experiences, when it is seen to also characterize most natural worldly perceptions and interactions, barring hypothetical non-intentional or non-dual consciousness (Henry, 2008; Husserl, 2019)?

(iii) It must be mentioned that Maslow used this term to qualify the highest level of self-development in his hierarchy of needs, following “self-actualization” needs (Maslow, 1943). In this context “self-transcendence” seems to refer to an overcoming of previous limitations, including outgrowing narrow egoic identifications, or to various forms of experiences of expansion perceived as being “beyond” other modes of experience. This is understandable, yet following our analyses, the term still appears as too specific, historically charged, and ambiguous to be a good candidate.

Thus, we have not found any existing term that is entirely appropriate for our goals. These are of course fine terms on their own and in their own contexts. However, we see the need for a dedicated terminology as has occurred with the development of most fields of knowledge (e.g., medicine or mathematics) to facilitate universal communication.

3.3 Emergent phenomena, experiences and effects

We hypothesize that if our understanding of the domain we have delineated is to be developed and scale globally, a key step is to develop dedicated terms that avoid the issues we outlined above that might prevent global adoption. The flip side of this thesis is our assertion that adoption of problematic terminology was and is a major factor in the failure of every previous attempt to integrate knowledge of the experiences in question into the global clinical and mental health mainstreams.

We also hypothesize that determining optimal clinically and scientifically operationalizable definitions and taxonomies of these phenomena, effects, and transformations that scale globally is a challenge which will require extensive basic and applied research, as well as global linguistic and conceptual negotiations and compromises.

As a first step in this direction, we propose to refer to these effects and experiences (as listed in the inventory), as “emergent phenomena, experiences and effects” (EPEEs henceforth), or sometimes “emergent experiences,” or “emergent phenomena,” which, depending on how they are related to, may be felt to be “emergent crises,” “emergent benefits,” or simply “emergence.”

This choice came from a long-term, collective process of trying to find the most scientifically descriptive, non-ontological, accurate, scalable term for this broad category of experiences, processes, and effects. We did not invent the term “emergence,” as it has been used in other disciplines (e.g., complexity science) for a long time. But we did notice a parallel with the way these disciplines use this term, noting that these experiences seem to “emerge” from an extremely complex system in ways that currently cannot be predicted by their currently known constituent parts or other underlying principles. We also noted a synchrony with Transpersonal Psychology and its notion of “spiritual emergence” but realized that it might not always be clear why certain effects might necessarily be described as “spiritual,” as discussed in section 3.2, hence our choice. We would like to thank and acknowledge Dr. Kathryn Devaney, who initially proposed the term, and the other early members of the consortium of researchers who coalesced around this shared concern to form Emergent Phenomenology Research Consortium31 for their valuable insights and innovations in initial and essential linguistic discussion. This terminology has started being used in recent academic literature (Salguero, 2023; Wright et al., 2023).

Here a phenomenon refers to a specific subjective sensation, perception, or object, a gestalt (see the definition above) which does not include the entirety of the field of experience or of a given duration of time. An experience is more “complete” — it includes the totality of the lived world of the subject for a given duration. Also, the term phenomenon is often used to point to a more “objective” event than the term experience, which tends to point to the subjective pole. An effect, in this context, can refer to a phenomenon or experience, when these are apprehended through the lens of their hypothetical cause, of which they are an effect. It is also used when studying the impacts, on various experiential or functional domains, of a given phenomenon or experience seen as the cause of these impacts, which can also be referred to as after-effects.

3.3.1 Emergent practices or modalities

We will refer to the intentional cultivation modalities associated with EPEEs as “emergent practices,” though this term realistically must encompass the circumstances that make their arising more likely, even if they were not intentional practices and occurred spontaneously. Intentionality is not necessary for a modality to increase the likelihood of emergent phenomena. Examples would include someone practicing meditation in a secular materialist tradition who was unaware of and uninterested in emergent phenomena and effects, or someone taking a psychedelic recreationally.

3.3.2 Process of emergence

Contrary to the synchronic phenomenology contained in the inventory, what we will call the “Process of emergence” includes a diachronic, developmental, or progressive element, however potentially non-linear, often relating to a series of emergent phenomena which have marked the subject, or perhaps produced some sort of transformation, regardless of the valuation of that transformation. Various developmental systems have been proposed for this sort of process over the millennia, as well as for the possible predicted sequences in which these might lead to a process of emergence.

We will now review potential arguments in favor of these linguistic choices.

3.4 Advantages and disadvantages of these terms

3.4.1 Advantages

From a clinical lens, we hypothesize that these terms are scalable, in the sense that they:

• Are simple, clear, and sufficiently free of cultural baggage to be used within clinical and scientific contexts,

• Are not proprietary, nor from a particular orthodoxy,

• Carry fewer connotations than many words such as “spiritual,” “religious,” or “mystical” (see below for a detailed discussion).

From a philosophical perspective, they are closer to an ideal of ontological neutrality, meaning they are relatively devoid of metaphysical content, assumptions, or implications. Obviously, there is a limit to “neutrality,” and some argue “methodological agnosticism” is in fact impossible or a hindrance (Blum, 2018). However, the reality of much of clinical experience is very aligned with the notion of ontological or methodological agnosticism, and this seems to be functional in practice. Good clinicians, and good emergent teachers, often avoid this issue in working with people to meet them where they are, establish therapeutic relationships, work with their assumptions and cultural conditioning, to promote good outcomes.

These terms avoid cultural appropriation or bias, and syncretism. From an anthropological lens, it is a neutral etic32 framework that allows the study of various religious or spiritual traditions with specific, emic cultural frameworks, while maintaining their integrity. Syncretism — the often imprecise and rough fitting amalgamation of various traditions, religious and spiritual frameworks and philosophies into a whole, is off-putting and often offensive to both orthodox traditions and beyond, as demonstrated by over 140 years of syncretic solutions failing to gain any significant traction in the clinical and scientific mainstream, thus posing a massive barrier to the ethical scaling of the research and study of this field.

We explicitly aim to avoid directly contradicting the core assumptions of major scientific and orthodox traditions, and instead adopt a clinically pragmatic stance which focuses on what frameworks add value to care, improve outcomes and human flourishing.

Other potential advantages are that the terms “emergence” and derivates add historical and epistemic connectedness, as they are auspiciously coherent with previous usages of similar terms to refer to the same general process, e.g., with the notion of spiritual emergence (Grof and Grof, 1989).

Semantically, they preserve and convey something of the upward movement which has often traditionally been associated with what we call the process of emergence, with the vocabulary of elevation being present in many spiritual tropes of the various religious or spiritual traditions, e.g., the ascent of mount Sinai (Judaism–Christianity); the ascent of mount Carmel or Epéktasis as “ascent toward God” in John Climacus (Christianity); anabasis/catabasis as the elevation/descent of the spirit in the Greek Mystery Schools; the ascent of Muhammad toward god in Quran, LIII, 4–10 (Islam); the contemplative process of rising up the jhānas, with the rarest and most refined of these modalizations being referred to as the higher jhānas (Buddhism); the movement toward “highest values” which defines spirituality according to Pargament et al. (2013); Plotinian “mystical ascent” (Mazur et al., 2021, chap. 4); and so on. We do not mean to imply that every “emergent process” necessarily leads “upward” to something better or higher, just to point the linguistic resonance with numerous traditional characterizations of the ultimate trajectory of these processes.

Etymologically, ex- means “out” and mergō “to dip, to immerse, to plunge.” This conveys something of the possible beneficial nature of these experiences and of the associated emergence process, which are often traditionally associated with soteriologies33 and interpreted as a process of purification of coming out of some undesirable moral or experiential predicament or state (sin, ignorance, dukkha, etc.) and even something of the notion of “conversion” or being “twice-born” (James, 2005).

Metaphorically, they reflect the possibly sudden mode of onset of EPEEs and discontinuous tipping points in emergent processes described in some traditions [e.g., Britton et al. (2014) argue that the course of meditative progress suggests a nonlinear multiphasic trajectory] — emerging from water happens gradually but there are discontinuities such as the precise moment when one begins to surface, or the moment when one is completely out of the water.

3.4.2 Disadvantages

Clearly, there is overlap with uses in other disciplines which may create confusion. The terms “emergence” and “emergent phenomena” (or perhaps more commonly, “emergent properties”) are indeed used in various disciplines such as in math, biology, cognitive science, economy, philosophy, and more. But this is also the case with, e.g., the word “organic,” which can qualify organic chemistry (all chemistry involving carbon), organic food (food that is grown without chemical fertilizers), organic art (spontaneous artistic expression), organic processes (processes of development that occur spontaneously/naturally in living beings), etc.

While there is indeed a semantic commonality, these are quite different meanings. Yet, few people would report any issues with this polysemy, as it is easy to differentiate between these various meanings based on context. Perhaps those who still feel the conflict with complexity science could simply use terms such as “emergent experience” or “emergent phenomenology.”

Another issue is that new words like we propose may not be seen favorably by those who have adopted other terminology in their work or practice over the years (or centuries). As we said, the solution here might be to consider these new terms (and further terminologies which may be proposed by others) as defining an etic framework, the use of which could remain limited within the community who work in the specialized field of research we believe is being defined here, and let emic frameworks be untouched by this and freely reject or adopt these terms. These questions are open for debate.

3.5 Clarifying thematic contours

As we alluded to earlier in this article, there are four central notions we wish to discuss in more detail to clarify their relationship with the way we conceptualize EPEEs. These are: (1) Altered-states of consciousness (ASCs), (2) Spirituality/Spiritual experiences, (3) Mysticism/Mystical Experiences and (4) Religion/Religious experiences.

3.5.1 Emergence and altered states of consciousness

As we alluded to in the introduction and when discussing the Altered-State Database, the notion of altered states of consciousness can be limiting and problematic when approaching EPEEs in the way we wish to. It may apply broadly to some of them, but when looked at in more detail, terminological issues with each word that composes the expression “altered” “states” of “consciousness” appear.

Indeed, the term state implies a rigidity or stability which is not a good description of the rapidly changing nature of experience (Le Blanc-Louvry, 2015; Vion-Dury and Mougin, 2016). Some more seemingly stable “states” sometimes arise, and that is of course reflected in the common usage of this term, but that is not always the case. It may sometimes cover up the often rich detail of the temporal shape of some or all of these “stable states,” including, e.g., the Buddhist jhānas. As a case in point, recent micro-phenomenological investigations into these “states” demonstrate that, in practice, they are developmentally and experientially richer and more complex than a formulaic description conveys (Sparby, 2019).

The notion of “alteration” also implies a baseline stable state that is then departed from or altered, but it is impossible to precisely identify such a reified, baseline state, since our levels of vigilance, attention, attitudes, paradigms, etc. constantly modulate the contents of our experience. In short, the phenomenal features of what Husserl called the “living present” is a “field of actuality” (De La Tremblaye and Bitbol, 2022) and changes continuously. This also poses important issues at a philosophical level (Vion-Dury and Mougin, 2016). Again, this may work in everyday language, but not in the context of a dedicated, systematic, precise technical lexicon.

Many traditions consider what some might consider as “altered” states to, in fact, represent natural and even expected manifestations of the process of emergence (Grabovac, 2014). This includes the development of, e.g., attentional expertise. Hence, the adjective seems inadequate in this context too, as is not in keeping with this specific developmental perspective and set of expectations, in the same way that it would be strange to call an adult an “altered baby” or adolescence an “altered state of consciousness” (with no disrespect implied to parents who do come to this functionally descriptive conclusion). Furthermore, not all emergent phenomena are associated with an emergent process: to illustrate this point, we can mention how not all psychedelic experiences, which might be powerfully “altered,” will necessarily trigger what we might consider a process of emergence. Not all emergent development is caused by intense or exotic experiences, either (Yaden and Newberg, 2022).

Conversely, some emergent traditions consider that the hypothetical “baseline state” that would be altered to become ASCs is in fact itself the “altered” and deluded one: for instance, the essence of mind schools of Tibetan Buddhism (Mahāmudrā and Dzogchen) consider the “ordinary mind” (sems) as a distortion or misinterpretation of “awake awareness” (rigpa) or the “natural state” (Bkra-shis-rnam-rgyal and Tweed, 2001; Bdud-ʼjoms-glin˙-pa and Wallace, 2016).

Furthermore, the notion is clearly not practically sufficient to refer to many experiences and effects reviewed in the inventory (Supplementary file S2), including but not limited to:

• Energy-like somatic experiences (e.g., sensations of a “vibration cascading through the body,” or “extremely painful energy flows” as reported in Cooper et al., 2021);

• Shifts in metaphysical beliefs, which can be triggered by meditation (Lindahl et al., 2017) and/or psychedelics (Timmermann et al., 2022), and influence outcomes (Lindahl et al., 2022a);

• Motor effects such as involuntary movements [Cooper et al. (2021) report “jumpiness,” “whole-body jerking,” “spontaneous […] back-bending,” and “shaking”], which are commonly reported spontaneous side-effects of meditation practice;

• Changes to basic wakefulness levels (Britton et al., 2014);

• Functional effects such as increased or decreased executive or cognitive function (Brook, 2021);

• Profound vocational and life-trajectory impacts (Nicholson, 2014);

• Rarer instances such as voluntarily induced “cessations of consciousness” which are clearly neither phenomena, experiences, nor states, since they are by definition devoid of any experiential content, but rather “events,” which can only be characterized somewhat indirectly (Berkovich-Ohana, 2017; Winter et al., 2020; Chowdhury et al., 2023; Laukkonen et al., 2023).

Evidently, such reports are not states per se, but they are not really “of consciousness” either, since they cover domains as varied as physiology, sensations, kinesthesis, behavior, function, baseline vigilance levels, etc. We could extend the definition of “consciousness” to include all these aspects into a pervasive “field of consciousness,” as do Vion-Dury and Mougin (2016), but then, what else could there be a state of? This would render the adjective redundant.

3.5.2 Emergence, religion, and spirituality

As quoted by Lukoff et al. (1998), the Thesaurus of Psychological Index Terms (Walker, 1991) states that religiosity “is associated with religious organizations and religious personnel” (p. 184) whereas spirituality refers to the “degree of involvement or state of awareness or devotion to a higher being or life philosophy. Not always related to conventional religious beliefs” (p. 208).

In the more recent American Psychological Association handbook of psychology, religion and spirituality, Pargament et al. (2013) provide similar definitions:

“We define spirituality as ‘the search for the sacred.’ […] The term sacred is used inclusively here to refer not only to concepts of God and higher powers but also to other aspects of life that are perceived to be manifestations of the divine or imbued with divine-like qualities, such as transcendence, immanence, boundlessness, and ultimacy (Pargament and Mahoney, 2005). Virtually any part of life, positive or negative — including beliefs, practices, experiences, relationships, motivations, art, nature, and war — can be endowed with sacred status. […] By search, we are referring to an ongoing journey, a process that begins with the discovery of something sacred.”

Their definition of religion is the following:

“Building on the work of Hill et al. (2000) and Pargament (1997), we define religion as ‘The search for significance that occurs within the context of established institutions that are designed to facilitate spirituality.’ The term search refers once again to the ongoing journey of discovery, conservation, and transformation. In this case, however, the destination of the search is ‘significance’: a term that encompasses a full range of potential goals, including those that are psychological (e.g., anxiety reduction, meaning, impulse control), social (e.g., belonging, identity, dominance), and physical (e.g., longevity, evolutionary adaptation, death) as well as those that are spiritual (Pargament, 1997; Mahoney and Thelen, 2010; see Part II of this volume). Religion occurs within the larger context of established institutions and traditions that have as their primary goal the facilitation of spirituality. In contrast to the modern tendency among scholars to dissociate spirituality from religion, our view is that spirituality represents the function most central to institutional religious life. It is the spiritual character of its mission that makes religious institutions distinctive; no other social institution has spirituality as its primary goal (Mahoney and Thelen, 2010).

Clearly, questions of “transcendence, immanence, boundlessness, and ultimacy” are recurring and perennial themes in some who report undergoing a process of emergence or non-developmental EPEEs. However, our phenomenological and clinical interests include a vast range of manifestations which are not always associated with these themes.

Many who experience emergent phenomena are indeed on a “quest,” and thus again there is some overlap with the notion of spirituality, but by all means, not all EPEEs represent “the discovery of something sacred” (Pargament et al., 2013) to those undergoing them, nor do they represent the beginning of a “process,” although, in the case of the “process of emergence,” as we conceive of it here, there is overlap.

Now, more crucially: it is true that each experience and effect described in the inventory could possibly be viewed or related to as spiritual in nature. But so could any aspect of life, as, per Pargament’s above definition, “virtually any part of life […] can be endowed with sacred status,” and spirituality is “the search for the sacred.” What is crucial to realize here is that, from this perspective, speaking of specifically spiritual experiences, with hypothetical essential phenomenal features, makes little sense, since the spiritual dimension of experiences depends entirely on how one relates to them at a reflexive level. Thus, strictly speaking, and using this definition, it follows that at the pre-reflexive level (Husserl, 2012; Vermersch, 2012, p. 138), there are not necessarily any intrinsically spiritual experiences. This label is one degree of elaboration too high. This is not in any way to disparage the use of such labels if they are of value, just to point out that, particularly when attempting to spread practical knowledge in various contexts, the insistence on the necessity of such labels may pose barriers to success.

This critique extends to all compounded expressions found in section 3.2 above, such as “spiritual emergence,” “spiritual experiences,” “spontaneous spiritual awakenings,” “spiritually transformative experiences,” etc.

Similarly, religious experience seems to be usually defined by its collective, social, and institutional context. This is a very common way of viewing religion. Yet, the same irresolvable contradiction immediately follows as in the previous paragraph. In theory, per Pargament’s definition, virtually any experience could be seen as religious, if related to as existing in a specifically collective/institutional context that seeks to produce significance and to foster the search for the sacred — spirituality — including shaking hands with someone or cutting one’s hair. In fact, this seems to be the case, as there are many practices broadly appraised as “religious” which entail exactly these sorts of actions (i.e., cutting one’s hair a certain way, or specific greeting ceremonies), and yet it seems difficult to relate these with the experiences and effects we speak about throughout the present article.

In short, the criteria that define spirituality and religion are not primarily phenomenological, but mostly cultural and contextual, related to individual and collective meaning-making, respectively. Meaning making is part of where the specific value of spirituality and religion lies. This is an important observation. It follows that, since our perspective is phenomenological, and our themes of interest are specific experiences and effects, we are interested in the pre-reflexive level associated with specific experiences and less about how they are related at the reflexive level. However, for our purposes here, we question the necessary and unquestioned use of labels such as spiritual or religious to broadly qualify this set of described and observed experiences and effects, because it:

• Dilutes the specific meaning of religion and spirituality,

• Sometimes adds confusing cultural overlays on EPEEs, and

• Impedes the globally scaling and practical application of a rich field of scientific and academic study and clinical practice to broad human detriment.

3.5.3 Emergence and mystical experience

As for mystical “states of consciousness,” the influence of William James’ seminal work, Varieties of Religious Experience, and that of W.T. Stace in Philosophy and Mysticism is such, that theirs seems the most adequate source to look at. These conceptualizations are what modern scales such as the Mystical Experience Questionnaire (MEQ) and Mysticism Scale (M-scale) are based on, and these are the ones used in many clinical trials seeking to assess the effects and outcomes associated with psychedelic use; thus, their clinical relevance is significant.

Let us begin with James. Lectures XVI and XVII in the series which make up The Varieties of Religious Experience treat at length of the topic of “mystical phenomena” (p. 378) because, according to James, “personal religious experience has its root and center in mystical states of consciousness” (p. 379). Here, James sets himself the task of showing the “reality of the states in question,” and the “paramount importance of their function” (ibid.) He proposes a definition of the states comprised in the “mystical group” (p. 384) as characterized by “four marks”: (1) Ineffability, (2) Noetic quality, (3) Transiency and (4) Passivity (pp. 380–384).

In Mysticism and Philosophy (Stace, 1987), W.T. Stace provides a summary of the common characteristics of what he calls “extrovertive” and “introvertive” mystical experiences.

Extrovertive mystical experiences involve:

• “Unifying vision – all things are one,

• An apprehension of the One [“The Divine” or “Ultimate Reality”] as an inner subjectivity, or life, in all things,

• A sense of objectivity or reality,

• Blessedness, peace, [bliss], etc.

• Feeling of the holy, sacred, or divine,

• Paradoxicality, and

• Alleged ineffability.”

Introvertive mystical experiences involve:

• “The unitary consciousness – the One, the void [“The Divine” or “Ultimate Reality”];

• pure consciousness

• Non-spatial, non-temporal sense of objectivity or reality

• Blessedness, peace, [bliss], etc.

• Feeling of the holy, sacred, or divine

• Paradoxicality, and

• Alleged ineffability.”

The aforementioned scales directly derive from these two definitions. Indeed, the Mystical Experience Questionnaire (MEQ) comprises 30 or 43 question items, depending on the version, divided into 6 domains (Barrett et al., 2015). These are:

1. A sense of unity,

2. Transcendence of time and space,

3. Ineffability and paradoxicality,

4. A sense of sacredness,

5. A noetic quality, and.

6. A deeply-felt positive mood.

The Mysticism Scale (M-scale) comprises three domains (Streib et al., 2020):

1. Extrovertive, with 2 sub-domains of Inner Subjectivity and Unity,

2. Introvertive, with 3 sub-domains of Timelessness/Spacelessness, Ego loss, Ineffability, and.

3. Interpretation with 3 sub-domains of Positive affect, Sacredness, and a Noetic quality.

From our present perspective, critical comparison of these scale domains and James’ and Stace’s criteria with our inventory of contemporary scientific literature, as well as with traditional texts, reveals the profound limitations of the ways this notion is defined by these authors, with:

1. The de facto exclusion of experiences and effects of a challenging nature such as the “Dark Nights” — of the “Soul,” “Senses,” or “Spirit” (Kornfield, 1993; St. John of the Cross, 2010; Lutkajtis, 2019c), often tellingly called “Mystical Nights” — which certainly cannot be characterized by a positive mood, nor necessarily by a short duration, nor any of the other criteria we just listed. However, these are a common and essential phase of spiritual development according to canonical Christian texts. Notice, that there are kinds of dark nights. One may think this is specific to some Christian authors. But a similar point can be made with the Buddhist notion of the “Dukkha ñanas” (Pali), meaning “Knowledges of Suffering,” a normative developmental phase within the context of Theravada Buddhist meditation theory (Kornfield, 1993; Mahāsī Sayadaw, 1994; Grabovac, 2014; Lutkajtis, 2019a,b, 2020). As their name suggests, these “stages” of deepening meditation include experiences of “fear,” “misery,” “disgust,” etc. Yet, in this traditional framework, they are preceded and followed by stages which could fit many or all of the above criteria. Also, notice again that several variants and phases of “knowledges of suffering” are traditionally distinguished. Even if one chose to consider that later commentarial texts like the Vissudhimagga (Buddhaghosa, 1991) where this model was elaborately described and expanded on beyond its roots in the Abhidhamma and Khuddaka Nikāya, are “inauthentic,” one could respond that some texts which are canonical in all branches of Buddhism [the Pali canon (Ñanamoli and Bodhi, 1995)] contain ample evidence that “mystical experience” is not just what James and Stace described. Beyond these two traditions, grief and trauma (Yaden and Newberg, 2022) and generally speaking suffering-related experiences acting as triggers of spiritual development is a well-documented phenomenon. In fact, one may even say that in various traditional texts, mystical life begins with suffering and systematically involve negative experiences, sometimes to extreme degrees. This is reflected in Joseph Campbell’s monomyth, or Hero’s journey, a universal model of the unfolding of narrative and mythological stories in world literature, where the hero enters the Underworld or Abyss, or undergoes some profoundly challenging Quest, before coming back transformed or renewed to the known world (Campbell, 2008). Obviously, challenging EPEEs abound in our inventory, such as negatively valenced and sometimes terrifying psychedelic experiences (“bad trips”). Yet these may have long-term positive effects (as well as further negative effects) on one’s spirituality and life in general, be existentially and paradigmatically transformative, and result in beneficial long-term outcomes. All these examples show that we should not frame “mystical” experiences and generally EPEEs as only “pleasant” and ignore or fail to properly categorize and study non-pleasant, sometimes challenging EPEEs, at the risk of fueling what has been described as the “overly positive presentation of meditation in the media” (Lutkajtis, 2019c). One may argue that contemporary research has developed specific instruments to that effect (e.g., the Challenging Experience Questionnaire) but it is also clear that appraising all experiences which do not fit a simplistic definition of mystical experience as “challenging experiences,” “adverse effects” or “adverse events” (Farias et al., 2020), is problematic.

2. These criteria also exclude what some have termed “Interactive-relational” experiences, i.e., seeming encounters with various types of entities or presences — which do not necessarily involve a sense of inner or outer unity, nor any other of these criteria. Such experiences were one of the most common type of experiences across all modalities in our inventory [see, e.g., Greyson and Stevenson (1980), Hartley and Daniels (2008), Charland-Verville et al. (2014), Maqueda et al. (2015), Camlin et al. (2018), Vieten et al. (2018), Sparby (2020), and Lawrence et al. (2022)]. This also means a large portion of world literature, such as prophetic, oracular, or visionary texts; archetypal psychology (Jung, 1980; Hillman, 2004); the effects of many psychedelic compounds (such as LSD, 5-Meo-DMT, Ibogaine, N,N-DMT, or Salvia Divinorum); the effects of various meditation practices; and even spontaneously occurring such experiences, or these that are reported in various contexts like having an accident or going through coma — these would all be disqualified as mystical experience. Yet to experiencers, these may be felt as deeply “mystical,” profound, and transformative. More importantly, from a pragmatic, human, as well as clinical point of view, such experiences are often causal and may have a wide range of impacts on real world personal, family, and societal outcomes.

3. As we just showed, beyond excluding important experience types, Jamesian and Stacian characteristics of mystical experiences lack differentiating power, as they could in fact correspond to several forms of emergent phenomena which are distinguished both in Christian mystical theology, and Buddhist meditative theory. For instance, within the developmental models we just presented, these could correspond, within Carmelite theory of mystical development, either to the initial fruits of practice for beginning meditators before they enter the unpleasant and challenging purification of the Dark Nights, and/or to later phases of practice. Similarly, within buddhist stages of insight meditation, “mystical experience” fits well with either the very early phases of meditation, or to the all-important fourth stage of “Arising and Passing Away,” which immediately precedes the “Dukkha ñanas,” or to the one that immediately follows these “Dukkha ñanas” (called “Equanimity”). The 4, 8 or 9 jhānas would likely all qualify as mystical experiences, yet they each represent specific, differentiated experiences. It is highly likely that this comparison could be extended to almost all other mystical traditions. Thus, as with most current taxonomies of what we call EPEEs, recent definitions of mystical experience lack a sense of a differential diagnosis of possible states and stages that might present very similarly in some particulars but yet possibly be developmentally quite different.

4. Overall, the “transiency,” “ineffability,” “noetic,” and “passivity” criteria in James do not stand scrutiny with either traditional, or contemporary qualitative research. Indeed:

• The question of ineffability, might be an invalid criterion all together. Difficulty articulating a novel experience happening at the pre-reflexive level is a well-known fact of life. That is a basic premise of phenomenological research, with qualitative methods such as micro-phenomenology having been designed, precisely, to help experiences make “what experiences are like” explicit (Petitmengin, 2006; Husserl, 2012; Vermersch, 2012; Petitmengin et al., 2017; Petitmengin et al., 2019). The (perfectly legitimate) sense that talking about a given event would somehow diminish its value, leading to a form of privacy or secrecy, is not exactly the same thing as that experience being impossible to express.

• As for transiency, traditional knowledge and recent research shows that various meditative states, sometimes highly refined and rare, such as Buddhist Nirodha Samāpatti can last quite a long-time (in the case of NS, Laukkonen et al. (2023) report a duration of 90 min, and the commentarial literature, such as the Visuddhimagga, reports such attainments may last for 7 or more days). Further, if one considers the “Dark Nights” and “Dhukka ñanas” as variants of mystical states, then these could actually last for months, years, or decades.

• The noetic criterion — meaning the experience involves a sense of “knowing,” or of perceiving something “true” — although sometimes seemingly very valid, should be used with discernment, as it can be misleading or even deceptive, and some (though not all!) forms of “noesis” are commonly described as pitfalls in many traditions. For instance the “Arising and Passing Away” stage we mentioned is described in some Buddhist mediation manuals as involving the arising of a “brilliant light,” “strong mindfulness,” “keen, strong, and lucid knowledge,” “strong faith,” “rapture in its five grades,” “tranquillity of mind,” “a very sublime feeling of happiness,” “energy,” “strong equanimity,” and “a subtle attachment” (Sayadaw, 1994). Yet these are clearly noted as “ten corruptions of insight” and “mistaking what is not the path for the path” (Sayadaw, 1994). The prescription here is to “purify” these corruptions by noticing that “The brilliant light, and the other things […] are not the path” and that “Delight in them is merely a corruption of insight” (Sayadaw, 1994). This applies to the noetic component, but also to other phenomenal features which are commonly attributed to mystical experiences by, e.g., Stace. Similar warnings around the early fruits of meditative practice can be found in Christian manuals (e.g., St. John of the Cross, 2010). In fact, classical mystical texts like the Cloud of Unknowing, would likely make the case that high mystical states rather involve a sense of unknowing, or not knowing (Wolters, 2001). The value of the sense of “knowing” in EPEEs is also questioned in contemporary research on psychedelic experiences (e.g., Timmermann et al., 2022 argue that “the ability of psychedelics to induce noetic feelings of revelation may enhance the significance and attribution of reality to specific beliefs, worldviews, and apparent memories […] might exacerbate the risk of iatrogenic complications that other psychotherapeutic approaches have historically faced, such as false memory syndrome”),

• The passivity criterion seems less ambiguous, but is nevertheless contradicted by the canonical description of, e.g., the first jhāna, which as we have seen involves intentionally “aiming” and “maintaining” one’s attention on the meditation object. Yet many would call the first jhāna a mystical experience.

The same terminological issues as outlined in section 3.2 apply, including:

Idiosyncratic use of the term “mystical.” Indeed, if we turn to classical early European mystical texts, such as those by late-antiquity author Plotinus, we find that they describe “mystical ascent,” the phases of which are described in Mazur et al. (2021), as culminating in a total “annihilation” into the “One” called henosis (Greek for “union”), which is followed by a “desubjectification.” Similarly, the last stage of the “path to God” as described by 13th-century German Mystics like Meister Eckhart or his student Tauler, is called a “modeless good” (De Libera, 1996), referring not as much to an “experience” with specific phenomenal features, but as a going beyond all manifest appearances (including going beyond feelings of bliss, of sacredness, of unity, of transcendence, etc.). Early mystical theologies like that of 5th- or 6th-century church father pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite (Pseudo-Dionysius, 1987) — a ubiquitous influence on medieval contemplatives — and later ones such as that by Marler and Rorem (1996) and St. John of the Cross (2010), respectively describe unio mystica34 as “an obscure and luminous darkness” and a “going forth from the flesh.” The same is true of other Abrahamic traditions, as described in Fisher (2022). All of these quintessentially mystical experiences seem to bear more resemblance with the Buddhist notion of “cessation of consciousness” than with Jamesian or Stacean “mystical experience,” which likely should be correlated with phenomena and experiences encountered at earlier phases of these developmental models. Note that in Theravada texts, even such “cessations of consciousness” are classified into various types depending on their setup, mode of entrance, and phenomena and effects after the exit.

Furthermore, the term “mystical” is to some degree culturally-bound. Why would the Latin-originated expression of “mystical experience” be adequate to speak about the experience of Buddhist, Muslim, or Hinduist contemplatives? Why not use their terms instead? Cultural and historical boundaries must be respected, but it must also be acknowledged that insisting on using them in research, clinical or scientific contexts creates problems, not only culturally, but also regarding scaling globally into clinical, public health, and scientific contexts.

Additional history and criticism of these definitions and the psychometric instruments that derive from them can be found in Taves (2020). The author also reminds us that, “When William James criticized the contemptuous disregard with which scientists treated the ‘mass of phenomena generally called mystical’ in 1890, he presupposed a widely accepted definition of mysticism that included ‘divinations, inspirations, demoniacal possessions, apparitions, trances, ecstasies, miraculous healings and productions of disease, and occult powers’” (Taves, 2020). Furthermore, “James also linked such experiences with drugs” (Taves, 2020), writing that, “The drunken consciousness is one bit of the mystic consciousness,” and with certain “pathological conditions” (James, 2005). It is only later that he, alongside others, adopted a “narrower definition” (Taves, 2020), crystallizing in Stace’s limiting, contradictory, and biased definition of mysticism, which would inform 20th century thinking and research. Clearly, James’ original view of mysticism was closer to what we call EPEEs. Thus, in many ways, we are returning to the original Jamesian spirit.

In sum, we see EPEEs as a specific group that is differentiated from the notions of ASCs, religious, spiritual, or mystical experiences (in the modern sense) in specific and crucial ways that should not be overlooked.

Moreover, most classifications of EPEEs that we are aware of, usually lack precise differentiating criteria along various axes, including but not limited to:

• Sequence (what is described or predicted to occur before and after),

• context,

• Neurophysiological correlates,

• Micro-phenomenological details,

• Consequences,

• Function (capabilities gained, modified, or lost), and

• The possibility of polyphasic presentations and non-linear developmental trajectories that might untangle such possible sources of confusion.

All of these should be part of a more mature and realistic clinical perspective.

For these reasons and because of the complex history, ambiguities, and difficulty in finding consensual definitions of terms like ASCs, religious, spiritual, or mystical experiences, it appears to us more desirable to leave traditional (emic) terms in their traditional context. One might argue that perhaps the issues come from the specific definitions we chose, and that updating these would yield something less problematic. But it seems to us that the problems are in some ways intractable.

Given human’s deep needs for meaning, EPEEs often have been personally or socially interpreted in various ways. A given manifestation may be given various appraisals, e.g., a single EPEE may be alternatively interpreted as signs of “possession,” “kundalini syndrome,” “meditative attainment,” or “functional neurological disorder.” It is highly likely that these frames, whether sacralizing or pathologizing, have an impact on outcomes (Lutkajtis, 2020a).

We need a broad, overarching, adaptable, scalable framework that can approach EPEEs without mobilizing such specific lenses necessarily, and instead leave space for what happens in real clinical and social situations. As noted above, misunderstanding, questioning, or contradicting meanings assigned to EPEEs, or, conversely, not having normalizing meanings and taxonomic, descriptive, and diagnostic labels to offer, may have implications for the therapeutic or teaching relationship. Creating expansile, adaptable, scalable frameworks and teaching skills that allow the benevolent and sophisticated navigation of the range of meanings in an ethical and culturally sensitive way is broadly understood in clinical situations to promote good outcomes, which is our primary concern here.

The confusion which persists in contemporary research demonstrates how much work is needed in this area. This issue is made more pressing by the fact that many people are currently engaging in what we call emergent practices outside of any institutionalized context, e.g., outside a personal spiritual quest. Yet they do often stumble upon EPEEs, even when recreationally using psychedelic substances, or when seeking simple stress-reduction by engaging in mindfulness-based interventions or meditation apps. They may end-up lost and without a map — as may well be any teachers of emergent practices, clinicians, or other mental health professionals they encounter as part of this process. In this context, it is vital we seek to integrate spiritual, clinical, and scientific paradigms to promote beneficial outcomes and avoid harmful ones.

3.5.4 The boundary question

An outstanding, critical concern, is about the exact boundaries of what qualifies as EPEEs or not.

At the “center,” where the effects are strong, and the impact significant and obvious, this is a relatively easy question. Dramatic “openings,” major “shifts,” powerful changes in perception: clearly these need to be included.

However, at the periphery, where, for example, for some, noticing thoughts are something they can observe might be a subtle shift (whereas it might be a dramatic revelation and/or existential challenge for others) and seem only slightly worthy of the designation “emergent phenomena.”

This is very much like defining the reasonable boundaries of the testable knowledge to be learned to be board certified in the medical field of, e.g., Emergency Medicine. From a certain point of view, care providers should know at least a little about nearly everything in medicine; yet, this being impossible, some lines must be drawn regarding what one can reasonably be required to know.

Thus, medical education focuses on core competencies, with the dual criteria that one must learn about the most frequently encountered problems, as well as those critical yet rare conditions that one might see once in a career or never but that it is absolutely required that one at least have some basic knowledge of. Cases falling outside this range may then be learned about with the assistance of a more knowledgeable colleague or specialist.

Similarly, for practical purposes, we begin at the relatively clear “center,” and will leave it for the progressing conversation to tease out which subtle effects are worthy of inclusion, from a clinical, pragmatic, and outcomes-based point of view — which likely be a long and complex conversation.

With this sort of pragmatism in mind, it seems possible to define a specialty focusing on EPEEs as an expansile, and perhaps, ultimately, somewhat vaguely bounded body of knowledge at the far edges.

4 Conclusion

In summary, we propose that our area of focus throughout this article constitutes a specific domain of human experience. EPEEs as we have defined them are not limited to any specific discipline, but could be variously approached through their physiological, phenomenological, anthropological, symbolic, functional, aesthetic, linguistic, and many other dimensions.

This is comparable to how fields like psychiatry cut across many disciplines, since psychiatric conditions and effects might involve numerous neurological, biochemical, social, functional, developmental, genetic/epigenetic, behavioral, metabolic, hormonal, symbolic, environmental, financial, legal, among other potential factors and consequences from many domains of concern both clinical and non-clinical which must be at least moderately well understood by numerous disciplines.

From a clinical perspective, we propose that the field of EPEEs, while potentially impacting and involving nearly every domain and system of medicine, is sufficiently complex and defined, likely requiring a unique enough set of skills and knowledge not adequately covered by existing specialties, to constitute its own specialty. We posit that the experiment of defining and creating this specialty would likely solve numerous problems currently faced by current research.

After years of careful discussion and reviews, exploration of ethical considerations and apparent mandates, and research, we believe in and advocate for using the term “emergence,” as well as its derivatives such as “emergent processes” and “emergent phenomena.”

We argue that these optimally balance scientific, philosophical, historic, anthropological, linguistic, conceptual, and globally clinically scalable considerations and so could be used as umbrella terms to describe this specific yet broad body of knowledge, research, and practice.

We understand and appreciate that advocating for specific terminological choices over this contentious field may invoke some challenging feelings and discussions, but we also feel strongly that the lack of such a non-problematic, precise, scalable, and appropriate umbrella terms has been such a significant impediment to the global study and scaling of this field as to be a substantial detriment to everyone involved in the process of emergence, and so feel this push is ethically warranted.

We recognize that this conclusion is reached by positing a set of optimal criteria which must be met (outlined in our introduction), and that this set of criteria itself is worthy of discussion and debate. We also look forward to the possibility that those more capable than us might come up with a term that not only meets all the criteria we propose, but also does this in a way that exceeds the term “emergence,” and invite those who care about this topic to engage in this ongoing conversation.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/Supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Author contributions

OS: Writing – original draft, Conceptualization, Data curation, Formal analysis, Methodology, Project administration, Supervision, Validation, Writing – review & editing. DI: Conceptualization, Funding acquisition, Resources, Supervision, Validation, Writing – review & editing.

Funding

The author(s) declare financial support was received for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article. OS received funding from Emergence Benefactors.

Acknowledgments

Our thanks go to the members of the Emergent Phenomenology Research Consortium, to the reviewers who commented on our initial manuscript, and, for their helpful input at various stages of writing, to John Bruder, Steven Egan, Chinmayee Hiremath, Marcin Kowrygo, Brian Spittles, Niels Lyngsø, and Teodora Vuković.

Conflict of interest

OS serves as an independent contractor for Emergence Benefactors (EB), a 501(c) (3) charity founded to fund and support the Emergent Phenomenology Research Consortium (EPRC) of which he is a member. DI was volunteer CEO, Board Chair, and philanthropic supporter of EB. He also volunteers to provide primary support for the EPRC.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Supplementary material

The Supplementary material for this article can be found online at: https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2024.1340335/full#supplementary-material

Footnotes

1. ^For further explanations on the background and rationale for this addition, see Lukoff et al. (1995).

2. ^E.g. “distressing experiences that involve loss or questioning of faith, problems associated with conversion to a new faith, or questioning of spiritual values that may not necessarily be related to an organized church or religious institution” (p. 835).

3. ^For more information about these four pillars of medical ethics, see, e.g., Varkey (2021) or Beauchamp and Childress (1979).

4. ^See for example the 1,000+ scientific articles and books we have gathered in a public Zotero collection we call the Emergence Research Database: https://www.zotero.org/ebresearch/collections/TAKNGM64.

5. ^“Mystical union.”

6. ^A greek term usually translated as a state “contemplation.”

7. ^Following Theoria, Theosis is the culmination of the practice of hesychasm in orthodox Christianity and can be translated as “glorification.”

8. ^A form of heightened awareness and vigilance.

9. ^See note 8.

10. ^An “intermediary absorptive state.”

11. ^A “station” or “stage” on the “mystical path.”

12. ^A “constriction.”

13. ^Variously meaning a “vision,” “union,” the “annihilation” of the “self” or a “cessation of consciousness.”

14. ^“Ecstasy.”

15. ^Functional impairment or “madness” related with spiritual practice.

16. ^Unification the field of consciousness, or concentration.

17. ^This translates to “wheel,” and refers to important physiological “energetic centers” in traditional Hindu anatomy.

18. ^A state, or stage, of liberation.

19. ^States of increasingly deep absorption.

20. ^Powers.

21. ^Both are forms of cessation (Pali nirodha) of consciousness and feelings.

22. ^Similar to the buddhist notion of access-concentration (Sayadaw, 1994), this refers to the “state of concentration necessary to successfully engage in specific contemplative practices, not just the result of them” (Fisher, 2022).

23. ^This and following terms, respectively, mean “slumber,” “dream” and “vision” — all referring to a form of “prophetic” contemplation.

24. ^A “place” of nothingness, “wherein all of one’s physical presence is transcended” (Fisher, 2022).

25. ^“Nullification” or “annihilation,” a technical term relating to states of absorption” (Fisher, 2022).

26. ^A radical change in life orientation.

27. ^A greek term used by Plotinus to designate the highest level of “mystical ascent,” which translates literally to “union.”

28. ^I.e. “a salient unity or intrinsic organization of diverse phenomenal features, based on reciprocal part-whole interactions” (Parnas, 2012).

29. ^These are vitakka (applied attention), vicāra (sustained attention), pīti (rapture), sukha (joy), ekaggata (one-pointedness) and upekkhā for the fourth and higher jhānas (Hagerty et al., 2013) — each of these has equivalents in the inventory.

30. ^On the spontaneous phenomenalization of our experiences into types, see Schuetz (1959) and Fernandez (2019).

31. ^See https://theeprc.org.

32. ^When studying a given ethnic group, anthropologists use the terms “emic” to refer to an attitude which mobilizes frameworks and views internal to a given cultural group, and “etic” when researchers instead use external concepts and notions.

33. ^Doctrines of salvation, often in a Christian context, but also can be used for general contexts, as we do here.

34. ^Mystical union.

References

Aixalà, M. B. (2022). Psychedelic integration: Psychotherapy for non-ordinary states of consciousness. First edn. Santa Fe: Synergetic Press.

Google Scholar

American Psychiatric Association . (2022). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th Edn., text rev). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association Publishing.

Google Scholar

Barber, M. D. (2021). On the Epoché in phenomenological psychology: a Schutzian response to Zahavi. J. Phenomenol. Psychol. 52, 137–156. doi: 10.1163/15691624-12341390

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, F. S., Johnson, M. W., and Griffiths, R. R. (2015). Validation of the revised mystical experience questionnaire in experimental sessions with psilocybin. J. Psychopharmacol. 29, 1182–1190. doi: 10.1177/0269881115609019

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Bdud-ʼjoms-glin˙-pa, S., and Wallace, B. A. (2016). Dudjom Lingpa’s visions of the great perfection.(First paperback edition). Sommerville: Wisdom Publications.

Google Scholar

Beauchamp, T. L., and Childress, J. F. (1979). Principles of biomedical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Benning, T. B., Harris, K. P., and Rominger, R. (2019). Delayed diagnosis of the physio-kundalini syndrome: case report and literature review. Spirit. Clin. Pract. 6, 194–212. doi: 10.1037/scp0000186

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Berkovich-Ohana, A. (2017). A case study of a meditation-induced altered state: increased overall gamma synchronization. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 16, 91–106. doi: 10.1007/s11097-015-9435-x

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Bitbol, M. (2014). La conscience a-t-elle une origine? Des neurosciences à la pleine conscience, une nouvelle approche de l’esprit. [Does consciousness have an origin? From neuroscience to mindfulness, a new approach to the mind]. Editions Flammarion. 748.

Google Scholar

Bitbol, M. (2019). Consciousness, being and life: phenomenological approaches to mindfulness. J. Phenomenol. Psychol. 50, 127–161. doi: 10.1163/15691624-12341360

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Bkra-shis-rnam-rgyalTweed, M. (2001). Clarifying the natural state: A principal guidance manual for Mahamudra. Trans. 1st Edn. eds. M. Tweed and E. Pema Kunsang Hong-Kong: Rangjung Yeshe.

Google Scholar

Blouin, P. S. (2022). La phénoménologie comme manière de vivre. [Phenomenology as a way of life]. Bucharest: Zeta Books.

Google Scholar

Blum, J. N. (2018). “Incapacitating scholarship: or, why methodological agnosticism is impossible” in The question of methodological naturalism. (Leiden, Boston: BRILL), 53–73.

Google Scholar

Bourguignon, E. (1973). Religion, altered states of consciousness and social change. Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press.

Google Scholar

Breeksema, J. J., and van Elk, M. (2021). Working with weirdness: A response to “moving past Mysticism in psychedelic science”. ACS Pharmacol Transl. Sci. 4, 1471–1474. doi: 10.1021/acsptsci.1c00149

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Britton, W. B., Lindahl, J. R., Cahn, B. R., Davis, J. H., and Goldman, R. E. (2014). Awakening is not a metaphor: the effects of Buddhist meditation practices on basic wakefulness. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 1307, 64–81. doi: 10.1111/nyas.12279

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Brook, M. G. (2021). Struggles reported integrating intense spiritual experiences: results from a survey using the integration of spiritually transformative experiences inventory. Psychol. Relig. Spiritual. 13, 464–481. doi: 10.1037/rel0000258

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Buddhaghosa (1991). The path of purification: Visuddhimagga. ed. Ñānamoli. Fifth ed. (Kandy, Sri Lanka: Buddhist Publication Society).

Google Scholar

Bünning, S., and Blanke, O. (2005). “The out-of body experience: precipitating factors and neural correlates” in Progress in brain research, vol. 150 (Elsevier), 331–606.

Google Scholar

Camlin, T. J., Eulert, D., Thomas Horvath, A., Bucky, S. F., Barsuglia, J. P., and Polanco, M. (2018). A phenomenological investigation into the lived experience of ibogaine and its potential to treat opioid use disorders. J Psychedel. Stud. 2, 24–35. doi: 10.1556/2054.2018.004

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Campbell, J. (2008). The hero with a thousand faces. 3rd Edn. Novato, California: New World Library.

Google Scholar

Castillo, R. J. (1990). Depersonalization and meditation. Psychiatry 53, 158–168. doi: 10.1080/00332747.1990.11024497

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Charland-Verville, V., Jourdan, J.-P., Thonnard, M., Ledoux, D., Donneau, A.-F., Quertemont, E., et al. (2014). Near-death experiences in non-life-threatening events and coma of different etiologies. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8:203. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00203

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Chowdhury, A., Lutterveld, R. V., Laukkonen, R. E., Slagter, H. A., Ingram, D. M., and Sacchet, M. D. (2023). Investigation of advanced mindfulness meditation “cessation” experiences using EEG spectral analysis in an intensively sampled case study. Neuropsychologia 190:108694. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2023.108694

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Cooper, D. J., Lindahl, J. R., Palitsky, R., and Britton, W. B. (2021). “Like a vibration cascading through the body”: energy-like somatic experiences reported by Western Buddhist meditators. Religions 12:1042. doi: 10.3390/rel12121042

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Corneille, J. S., and Luke, D. (2021). Spontaneous spiritual awakenings: phenomenology, altered states, individual differences, and well-being. Front. Psychol. 12. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.720579

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Cuthbert, B. N., and Insel, T. R. (2013). Toward the future of psychiatric diagnosis: The seven pillars of RDoC. BMC Med. 11:126. doi: 10.1186/1741-7015-11-126

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

De la Tremblaye, L., and Bitbol, M. (2022). Towards a phenomenological constitution of quantum physics: a QBist approach. Mind Matter 20, 35–62.

Google Scholar

De Libera, A. (1996). Eckhart, Suso, Tauler et la divinisation de l'homme. [Eckhart, Suso, Tauler and the divinization of man]. Paris: Bayard. 245.

Google Scholar

Depraz, N. (2008). Le corps glorieux: phénomenologie pratique de la Philocalie des Pères du désert et des Pères de l’Église. [The glorious body: A practical phenomenology of the Philocalia of the desert fathers and the church fathers]. Louvain-la-Neuve, Dudley: Éditions de l’Institut supérieur de philosophie; Peeters.

Google Scholar

Farias, M., Maraldi, E., Wallenkampf, K. C., and Lucchetti, G. (2020). Adverse events in meditation practices and meditation-based therapies: a systematic review. Acta Psychiatr. Scand. 142, 374–393. doi: 10.1111/acps.13225

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fernandez, A. V. (2019). Phenomenology and dimensional approaches to psychiatric research and classification. Philos. Psychiatry Psychol. 26, 65–75. doi: 10.1353/ppp.2019.0004

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fink, E. (1995). Sixth Cartesian meditation: The idea of a transcendental theory of method. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Google Scholar

Fisher, N. E. (2019). Dark nights and nonlinear paths in Western Abrahamic contemplative traditions. UC Santa Barbara. ProQuest ID: Fisher_ucsb_0035N_14611. Merritt ID: ark:/13030/m5j159mc. Available at: https://escholarship.org/uc/item/2pv5c4tp

Google Scholar

Fisher, N. E. (2022). Flavors of ecstasy: states of absorption in Islamic and Jewish contemplative traditions. Religions 13:935. doi: 10.3390/rel13100935

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Galante, J., Grabovac, A., Wright, M., Ingram, D. M., Van Dam, N. T., Sanguinetti, J. L., et al. (2023). A framework for the empirical investigation of mindfulness meditative development. Mindfulness 14, 1054–1067. doi: 10.1007/s12671-023-02113-8

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Grabovac, A. (2014). The stages of insight: clinical relevance for mindfulness-based interventions. Mindfulness 6, 589–600. doi: 10.1007/s12671-014-0294-2

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Greyson, B., and Stevenson, I. (1980). The phenomenology of near-death experiences. Am. J. Psychiatry 137, 1193–1196. doi: 10.1176/ajp.137.10.1193

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Grof, S., and Grof, C. (1989). Spiritual emergency: When personal transformation becomes a crisis (1st ed). Tarcher: Distributed by St. Martin’s Press.

Google Scholar

Hadot, P. (2002). Exercices spirituels et philosophie antique. [Spiritual exercises and ancient philosophy]. (Nouv. éd. rev. et augm). Paris: Albin Michel. 416.

Google Scholar

Hagerty, M. R., Isaacs, J., Brasington, L., Shupe, L., Fetz, E. E., and Cramer, S. C. (2013). Case study of ecstatic meditation: fMRI and EEG evidence of self-stimulating a reward system. Neural Plast. 2013:653572. doi: 10.1155/2013/653572

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hanley, A. W., Dambrun, M., and Garland, E. L. (2020). Effects of mindfulness meditation on self-transcendent states: perceived body boundaries and spatial frames of reference. Mindful. 11, 1194–1203. doi: 10.1007/s12671-020-01330-9

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hartley, J., and Daniels, M. (2008). A grounded theory investigation into negative paranormal or spiritual experience, based on the ‘diabolical mysticism’ of William James. Transpersonal Psychology Review 12, 51–72. doi: 10.53841/bpstran.2008.12.1.51

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Henry, M. (2008). Material phenomenology. 1st Edn. New York: Fordham University Press.

Google Scholar

Hill, P. C., Pargament, K. I., Hood, R. W., McCullough, M. E.Jr., Swyers, J. P., et al. (2000). Conceptualizing religion and Spirituality: points of commonality, points of departure. J. Theory Soc. Behav. 30, 51–77. doi: 10.1111/1468-5914.00119

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hillman, J. (2004). Archetypal psychology. Rev. and expanded 3rd Edn. Putnam, Connecticut: Spring Publications.

Google Scholar

Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2013). Systematicity: The nature of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Hulin, M. (2008). “La mystique sauvage. Aux antipodes de l'esprit” in Wild mystique. In the antipodes of the mind (Presses Universitaires de France).

Google Scholar

Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of the European sciences and transcendental philosophy. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

Google Scholar

Husserl, E. (2012). Ideas: General introduction to pure phenomenology. London, New York: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Husserl, E. (2019). The phenomenology of internal time-consciousness (second printing). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Google Scholar

James, W. (2005). The varieties of religious experience: A study in human nature: Being the Gifford lectures on natural religion delivered at Edinburgh in 1901–1902. Boston: Adamant Media Corporation.

Google Scholar

Jung, C. G. (1980). The archetypes and the collective unconscious. 2nd Edn: Princeton University Press.

Google Scholar

Jung, C. G. (1989). Memories, dreams, reflections. Rev. Edn. New York: Vintage Books.

Google Scholar

Kant, I. (2007). Critique of pure reason (M. Weigelt, Ed.; F. M. Müller, trans.) London: Penguin books. 708.

Google Scholar

Kason, Y. (2019). Touched by the light. Exploring Spiritually Transformative Experiences: Dundurn Press.

Google Scholar

Kornfield, J. (1993). A path with heart: A guide through the perils and promises of spiritual life. New York: Bantam Books.

Google Scholar

Lapassade, G. (1987). États modifiés de la conscience [Altered-States of Consciousness]. Paris: Éditions PUF.

Google Scholar

Laukkonen, R. E., Sacchet, M. D., Barendregt, H., Devaney, K. J., Chowdhury, A., and Slagter, H. A. (2023). “Cessations of consciousness in meditation: advancing a scientific understanding of nirodha samāpatti” in Progress in brain research (Elsevier), S0079612322001984.

Google Scholar

Lawrence, D. W., Carhart-Harris, R., Griffiths, R., and Timmermann, C. (2022). Phenomenology and content of the inhaled N, N-dimethyltryptamine (N, N-DMT) experience. Sci. Rep. 12:8562. doi: 10.1038/s41598-022-11999-8

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Le Blanc-Louvry, I. (2015). Épaisseur spatialisante de la conscience. [spatializing thickness of consciousness]. [Doctoral Dissertation, Université de Rouen]. 601. Available at: https://www.theses.fr/2015ROUEL006

Google Scholar

Lindahl, J. R., Britton, W. B., and Cooper, D. J. (2022b). Fear and terror in Buddhist meditation: A cognitive model for meditation-related changes in arousal and affect. J. Cognit. Historiograp. 7. doi: 10.1558/jch.22807

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lindahl, J. R., Cooper, D. J., Fisher, N. E., Kirmayer, L. J., and Britton, W. B. (2020). Progress or pathology? Differential diagnosis and intervention criteria for meditation-related challenges: perspectives from Buddhist meditation teachers and practitioners. Front. Psychol. 11:1905. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01905

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lindahl, J. R., Fisher, N. E., Cooper, D. J., Rosen, R. K., and Britton, W. B. (2017). The varieties of contemplative experience: A mixed-methods study of meditation-related challenges in Western Buddhists. PLoS One 12:e0176239. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0176239

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lindahl, J. R., Palitsky, R., Cooper, D. J., and Britton, W. B. (2022a). The roles and impacts of worldviews in the context of meditation-related challenges. Transcult. Psychiatry 60, 637–650. doi: 10.1177/13634615221128679

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Locke, R. G., and Kelly, E. F. (1985). A preliminary model for the cross-cultural analysis of altered states of consciousness. Ethos 13, 3–55. doi: 10.1525/eth.1985.13.1.02a00010

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Louchakova, O. (2006). “Ontopoiesis and Spiritual Emergence: Bridging Tymieniecka’s Phenomenology of Life and Transpersonal Psychology” in Phenomenology of Life from the Animal Soul to the Human Mind.. ed. A.-T. Tymieniecka (Netherlands: Springer), 94, 43–68.

Google Scholar

Lukoff, D., Lu, F. G., and Turner, R. (1995). Cultural considerations in the assessment and treatment of religious and spiritual problems. Psychiatr. Clin. N. Am. 18, 467–485. doi: 10.1016/S0193-953X(18)30035-2

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lukoff, D., Lu, F., and Turner, R. (1998). From spiritual emergency to spiritual problem: The transpersonal roots of the new DSM-IV category. J. Humanist. Psychol. 38, 21–50. doi: 10.1177/00221678980382003

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lundh, L.-G. (2022). Experimental phenomenology as an approach to the study of contemplative practices. Front. Psychol. 12:751298. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.751298

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lutkajtis, A. (2019a). Delineating the ‘dark night’ in Buddhist postmodernism. Lit. Aesthet. 29.

Google Scholar

Lutkajtis, A. (2019b). The dark side of dharma: meditation, madness and other maladies of the contemplative path. London: Aeon.

Google Scholar

Lutkajtis, A. (2019c). “The answer to all your problems?” The overly positive presentation of meditation in the media. J. Acad. Study Relig. 32, 49–71. doi: 10.1558/jasr.37863

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lutkajtis, A. (2020a). Lost saints: Desacralization, spiritual abuse and magic mushrooms. Fieldwork Relig. 14, 118–139. doi: 10.1558/firn.40554

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lutkajtis, A. (2020b). Meditation, madness and other maladies of the contemplative path. London: Aeon.

Google Scholar

Mahoney, J., and Thelen, K. (2010). “A gradual theory of institutional change” in Explaining institutional change: Ambiguity, agency, and power. eds. J. Mahoney and K. Thelen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Google Scholar

Maqueda, A. E., Valle, M., Addy, P. H., Antonijoan, R. M., Puntes, M. C., Coimbra, J., et al. (2015). Salvinorin-A induces intense dissociative effects, blocking external sensory perception and modulating Interoception and sense of body ownership in humans. Int. J. Neuropsychopharmacol. 18:pyv065. doi: 10.1093/ijnp/pyv065

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Marler, J. C., and Rorem, P. (1996). Pseudo-Dionysius: A commentary on the texts and an introduction to their influence. J. Am. Orient. Soc. 116:305. doi: 10.2307/605737

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Martial, C., Cassol, H., Charland-Verville, V., Pallavicini, C., Sanz, C., Zamberlan, F., et al. (2019). Neurochemical models of near-death experiences: A large-scale study based on the semantic similarity of written reports. Conscious. Cogn. 69, 52–69. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2019.01.011

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Maslow, A. H. (1943). A theory of human motivation. Psychol. Rev. 50, 370–396. doi: 10.1037/h0054346

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Maslow, A. H. (2014). Religions, values, and peak-experiences. United States: Stellar Books.

Google Scholar

Mazur, A. J., Burns, D. M., Corrigan, K., Miroshnikov, I., Rasimus, T., and Turner, J. D. (2021). The Platonizing Sethian background of Plotinus’s mysticism. Rev Edn. Leiden, Boston: Brill.

Google Scholar

Miller, W. R., and C'de Baca, J. (2001). Quantum change: When epiphanies and sudden insights transform ordinary lives. New York: Guilford Press.

Google Scholar

Mitchell, J. M., Ot’alora, G. M., van der Kolk, B., Shannon, S., Bogenschutz, M., Gelfand, Y., et al. (2023). MDMA-assisted therapy for moderate to severe PTSD: a randomized, placebo-controlled phase 3 trial. Nat. Med. 29, 2473–2480. doi: 10.1038/s41591-023-02565-4

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Moreira-Almeida, A., Sharma, A., van Rensburg, B. J., Verhagen, P. J., and Cook, C. C. (2016). WPA position statement on Spirituality and religion in psychiatry. World Psychiatry 15, 87–88. doi: 10.1002/wps.20304

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Mudgal, V., Dhakad, R., Mathur, R., Sardesai, U., and Pal, V. (2021). Astral projection: A strange out-of-body experience in dissociative disorder. Cureus. 13:e17037. doi: 10.7759/cureus.17037

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Ñanamoli, B., and Bodhi, B. (1995). “The middle length discourses of the Buddha” in A translation of the Majjhima Nikaya. ed. M. Nisargadatta (Somerville, MA: Wisdom Publication).

Google Scholar

National Institute of Mental Health . (n.d.) Development and definitions of the RDoC domains and constructs. Available at: https://www.nimh.nih.gov/research/research-funded-by-nimh/rdoc/development-and-definitions-of-the-rdoc-domains-and-constructs.

Google Scholar

Nicholson, P. T. (2014). Psychosis and paroxysmal visions in the lives of the founders of world religions. J. Neuropsychiatry Clin. Neurosci. 26, E13–E14. doi: 10.1176/appi.neuropsych.12120412

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Page, M. J., McKenzie, J. E., Bossuyt, P. M., Boutron, I., Hoffmann, T. C., Mulrow, C. D., et al. (2021). The PRISMA 2020 statement: an updated guideline for reporting systematic reviews. BMJ 372. doi: 10.1136/bmj.n71

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pargament, K. I. (1997). The psychology of religion and coping: Theory, research, practice. New York, London: Guilford Press.

Google Scholar

Pargament, K. I., and Mahoney, A. (2005). Sacred matters: sanctification as a vital topic for the psychology of religion. Int. J. Psychol. Relig. 15, 179–198. doi: 10.1207/s15327582ijpr1503_1

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pargament, K. I., Mahoney, A., Exline, J., Jones, J. W., and Shafranske, E. P. (2013). “Envisioning an integrative paradigm for the psychology of religion and spirituality” in APA handbook of psychology, religion, and spirituality (Vol 1): Context, theory, and research. eds. K. I. Pargament, J. J. Exline, and J. W. Jones (Washington: American Psychological Association), 3–19.

Google Scholar

Parnas, J. (2012). The core gestalt of schizophrenia. World Psychiatry 11, 67–69. doi: 10.1016/j.wpsyc.2012.05.002

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Petitmengin, C. (2006). Describing one’s subjective experience in the second person: an interview method for the science of consciousness. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 5, 229–269. doi: 10.1007/s11097-006-9022-2

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Petitmengin, C., Remillieux, A., and Valenzuela-Moguillansky, C. (2019). Discovering the structures of lived experience: towards a micro-phenomenological analysis method. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 18, 691–730. doi: 10.1007/s11097-018-9597-4

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Petitmengin, C., van Beek, M., Bitbol, M., Nissou, J.-M., and Roepstorff, A. (2017). Que vit le méditant ? Méthodes et enjeux d’une description micro-phénoménologique de l’expérience méditative. [What is it like to meditate?: methods and issues for a micro-phenomenological description of meditative experience]. Intellectica. Revue de l’Association pour la Recherche Cognitive. 67, 219–242. doi: 10.3406/intel.2017.1843

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Piarulli, A., Zaccaro, A., Laurino, M., Menicucci, D., De Vito, A., Bruschini, L., et al. (2018). Ultra-slow mechanical stimulation of olfactory epithelium modulates consciousness by slowing cerebral rhythms in humans. Sci. Rep. 8:6581. doi: 10.1038/s41598-018-24924-9

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pradelle, D. (2008). La constitution des idéalités est-elle une création? [Is the constitution of idealities a creation?]. Etudes Philos. 85, 227–251. doi: 10.3917/leph.082.0227

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Prugger, J., Derdiyok, E., Dinkelacker, J., Costines, C., and Schmidt, T. T. (2022). The altered states database: psychometric data from a systematic literature review. Scient. Data 9:720. doi: 10.1038/s41597-022-01822-4

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pseudo-Dionysius, (1987). Pseudo-Dionysius: the complete works. ed. P. Rorem (Trans). (Netherlands: Springer) New York: Paulist Press.

Google Scholar

Rose, K. (2016). Yoga, meditation and Mysticism. Contemplative universals and meditative landmarks. Bloomsbury.

Google Scholar

Salguero, C. P. (2023). “Meditation sickness” in medieval Chinese Buddhism and the contemporary west. J. Buddh. Ethics 30:45.

Google Scholar

Sandilands, O. (2019). Comparative phenomenology of aesthetic and meditative experiences [Master’s thesis]. Paris: École des Hautes Études en Sciences Sociales.

Google Scholar

Sartre, J.-P. (1957). The transcendence of the Ego: An existentialist theory of consciousness. New York: Octagon Books.

Google Scholar

Sayadaw, Mahāsī . (1994). The Progress of insight.

Google Scholar

Schlosser, M., Sparby, T., Vörös, S., Jones, R., and Marchant, N. L. (2019). Unpleasant meditation-related experiences in regular meditators: prevalence, predictors, and conceptual considerations. PLoS One 14:e0216643. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0216643

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Schmidt, T. T., and Berkemeyer, H. (2018). The altered states database: psychometric data of altered states of consciousness. Front. Psychol. 9:1028. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01028

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Schuetz, A. (1959). Type and Eidos in Husserl’s late philosophy. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 20:147. doi: 10.2307/2104353

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Sparby, T. (2017). The nature of contemplative science and some prospects for its future development. J. Conscious. Stud. 24, 226–250.

Google Scholar

Sparby, T. (2019). Phenomenology and contemplative universals: The meditative experience of Dhyana, coalescence, or access concentration. J. Conscious. Stud. 26, 130–156.

Google Scholar

Sparby, T. (2020). Body, soul, and Spirit: an explorative qualitative study of Anthroposophic meditation and spiritual practice. Religions 11:314. doi: 10.3390/rel11060314

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Sparby, T., and Sacchet, M. D. (2022). Defining meditation: foundations for an activity-based phenomenological classification system. Front. Psychol. 12:795077. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.795077

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Spittles, B. (2022). Psychosis, psychiatry and Psychospiritual considerations: Engaging and better understanding the madness and spiritual emergence Nexus. London: Aeon Books.

Google Scholar

St. John of the Cross (2010). Dark night of the soul, Gastonia: TAN Books.

Google Scholar

Stace, W. T. (1987). Mysticism and philosophy. ed. J. P. Tarcher (New York: Distributed by St. Martin’s Press).

Google Scholar

Stone, O., and Zahavi, D. (2021). Phenomenology and mindfulness. J. Conscious. Stud. 28, 158–185.

Google Scholar

Streib, H., Klein, C., Keller, B., and Hood, R. (2020). The Mysticism Scale as Measure for Subjective Spirituality in A. L. Ai, P. Wink, R. F. Paloutzian, and K. A. Harris. (2021). Assessing Spirituality in a diverse world. Spring. Int. Pub. 467–491.

Google Scholar

Tart, C. T. (1969). Altered states of consciousness: A book of readings. New York: Wiley.

Google Scholar

Taves, A. (2020). Mystical and other alterations in sense of self: an expanded framework for studying nonordinary experiences. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 15, 669–690. doi: 10.1177/1745691619895047

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Timmermann, C., Kettner, H., Letheby, C., Roseman, L., Rosas, F. E., and Carhart-Harris, R. L. (2021). Psychedelics alter metaphysical beliefs. Sci. Rep. 11:22166. doi: 10.1038/s41598-021-01209-2

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Timmermann, C., Watts, R., and Dupuis, D. (2022). Towards psychedelic apprenticeship: developing a gentle touch for the mediation and validation of psychedelic-induced insights and revelations. Transcult. Psychiatry 59, 691–704. doi: 10.1177/13634615221082796

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Tintinalli, J. E., Stapczynski, J. S., Ma, O. J., Yealy, D. M., and Meckler, G. D. (2020). Tintinalli’s emergency medicine: a comprehensive study guide, (Ninth edition). (New York: McGraw-Hill Education).

Google Scholar

Van Dam, N. T., Van Vugt, M. K., Vago, D. R., Schmalzl, L., Saron, C. D., Olendzki, A., et al. (2018). Mind the hype: A critical evaluation and prescriptive agenda for research on mindfulness and meditation. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 13, 36–61. doi: 10.1177/1745691617709589

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Varkey, B. (2021). Principles of clinical ethics and their application to practice. Med. Princ. Pract. 30, 17–28. doi: 10.1159/000509119

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Vermersch, P. (2012). Explicitation et phénoménologie: vers une psychophénoménologie. [Explicitation and phenomenology: towards a psychophenomenology]. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. 30

Google Scholar

Vieten, C., and Scammell, S. (2015). Spiritual and religious competencies in clinical practice : New Harbinger Publications, Inc.

Google Scholar

Vieten, C., Wahbeh, H., Cahn, B. R., MacLean, K., Estrada, M., Mills, P., et al. (2018). Future directions in meditation research: recommendations for expanding the field of contemplative science. PLoS One 13:e0205740. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0205740

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Vion-Dury, J., and Mougin, G. (2016). Modalisations of the consciousness field: a phenomenological and morphodynamic approach. PSN - Psychiatrie, sciences humaines, neurosciences. hal-01580235

Google Scholar

Wahbeh, H., Sagher, A., Back, W., Pundhir, P., and Travis, F. (2018). A systematic review of transcendent states across meditation and contemplative traditions. Explore 14, 19–35. doi: 10.1016/j.explore.2017.07.007

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Walker, A. (Ed.) (1991). Thesaurus of psychological index terms. 6th Edn. Arlington: American Psychological Association.

Google Scholar

Walls, R. M., Hockberger, R. S., Gausche-Hill, M., Erickson, T., and Wilcox, S. (Eds.) (2022). Rosen's emergency medicine: Concepts and clinical practice. 10th Edn. Philadelphia: Elsevier.

Google Scholar

Winter, U., LeVan, P., Borghardt, T. L., Akin, B., Wittmann, M., Leyens, Y., et al. (2020). Content-free awareness: EEG-fcMRI correlates of consciousness as such in an expert meditator. Front. Psychol. 10:3064. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.03064

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wolters, C. (2001). The cloud of unknowing and other works. New York: Penguin Books.

Google Scholar

Woollacott, M. H., Kason, Y., and Park, R. D. (2021). Investigation of the phenomenology, physiology and impact of spiritually transformative experiences – kundalini awakening. Explore 17, 525–534. doi: 10.1016/j.explore.2020.07.005

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

World Health Organization (2019). International statistical classification of diseases and related health problems. 11th Edn.

Google Scholar

World Health Organization, Quality of Life Spirituality, Religion and Personal Beliefs Group (2006). A cross-cultural study of spirituality, religion, and personal beliefs as components of quality of life. Social Sci. Med. 62, 1486–1497. doi: 10.1016/j.socscimed.2005.08.001

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wright, M. J., Sanguinetti, J. L., Young, S., and Sacchet, M. D. (2023). Uniting contemplative theory and scientific investigation: toward a comprehensive model of the mind. Mindfulness 14, 1088–1101. doi: 10.1007/s12671-023-02101-y

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Yaden, D. B., and Newberg, A. (2022). The varieties of spiritual experience: 21st century research and perspectives : Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Keywords: meditation, psychedelics, emergence, phenomenology, experience, medicine, ethics, emergent phenomena

Citation: Sandilands O and Ingram DM (2024) Documenting and defining emergent phenomenology: theoretical foundations for an extensive research strategy. Front. Psychol. 15:1340335. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2024.1340335

Received: 17 November 2023; Accepted: 24 June 2024;
Published: 10 July 2024.

Edited by:

Poppy L. A. Schoenberg, Vanderbilt University Medical Center, United States

Reviewed by:

Violeta Schubert, The University of Melbourne, Australia
Jaan Aru, University of Tartu, Estonia
Afra Wohlschlaeger, Technical University of Munich, Germany

Copyright © 2024 Sandilands and Ingram. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Olivier Sandilands, [email protected]

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.