Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 4

Aristotle's concept of ideal tragic hero: Hamartia

No passage in “The Poetics” with the exception of the Catharsis phrase


has attracted so much critical attention as his ideal of the tragic hero.

The function of a tragedy is to arouse the emotions of pity and fear and
Aristotle deduces the qualities of his hero from this function. He should be
good, but not perfect, for the fall of a perfect man from happiness into
misery, would be unfair and repellent and will not arouse pity. Similarly,
an utterly wicked person passing from happiness to misery may satisfy our
moral sense, but will lack proper tragic qualities. His fall will be well-
deserved and according to ‘justice’. It excites neither pity nor fear. Thus
entirely good and utterly wicked persons are not suitable to be tragic
heroes.

Similarly, according to Aristotelian law, a saint would be unsuitable as a


tragic hero. He is on the side of the moral order and hence his fall
shocks and repels. Besides, his martyrdom is a spiritual victory which
drowns the feeling of pity. Drama, on the other hand, requires for its
effectiveness a militant and combative hero. It would be important to
remember that Aristotle’s conclusions are based on the Greek drama and
he is lying down the qualifications of an ideal tragic hero. He is here
discussing what is the very best and not what is good. Overall, his views
are justified, for it requires the genius of a Shakespeare to arouse
sympathy for an utter villain, and saints as successful tragic heroes have
been extremely rare.

Having rejected perfection as well as utter depravity and villainy, Aristotle


points out that:

“The ideal tragic hero … must be an intermediate kind of person, a man not pre-eminently virtuous and
just, whose misfortune, however, is brought upon him not by vice or depravity but by some error of
judgment.”

The ideal tragic hero is a man who stands midway between the two
extremes. He is not eminently good or just, though he inclines to the side
of goodness. He is like us, but raised above the ordinary level by a
deeper vein of feeling or heightened powers of intellect or will. He is
idealized, but still he has so much of common humanity as to enlist our
interest and sympathy.

The tragic hero is not evil or vicious, but he is also not perfect and his
disaster is brought upon him by his own fault. The Greek word used here
is “Hamartia” meaning “missing the mark”. He falls not because of the
act of outside agency or evil but because of Hamartia or “miscalculation”
on his part. Hamartia is not a moral failing and it is unfortunate that it
was translated as “tragic flaw” by Bradley. Aristotle himself distinguishes
Hamartia from moral failing. He means by it some error or judgment. He
writes that the cause of the hero’s fall must lie “not in depravity, but in
some error or Hamartia on his part”. He does not assert or deny
anything about the connection of Hamartia with hero’s moral failings.

“It may be accompanied by moral imperfection, but it is not itself a moral imperfection, and in the purest
tragic situation the suffering hero is not morally to blame.”

Thus Hamartia is an error or miscalculation, but the error may arise from
any of the three ways: It may arise from “ignorance of some fact or
circumstance”, or secondly, it may arise from hasty or careless view of
the special case, or thirdly, it may be an error voluntary, but not
deliberate, as acts committed in anger. Else and Martian Ostwald interpret
Hamartia and say that the hero has a tendency to err created by lack of
knowledge and he may commit a series of errors. This tendency to err
characterizes the hero from the beginning and at the crisis of the play it
is complemented by the recognition scene, which is a sudden change
“from ignorance to knowledge”.

In fact, Hamartia is a word with various shades of meaning and has been
interpreted by different critics. Still, all serious modern Aristotelian
scholarship agreed that Hamartia is not moral imperfection. It is an error
of judgment, whether arising from ignorance of some material circumstance
or from rashness of temper or from some passion. It may even be a
character, for the hero may have a tendency to commit errors of judgment
and may commit series of errors. This last conclusion is borne out by the
play Oedipus Tyrannus to which Aristotle refers time and again and which
may be taken to be his ideal. In this play, hero’s life is a chain or
errors, the most fatal of all being his marriage with his mother. If King
Oedipus is Aristotle’s ideal hero, we can say with Butcher that: “His
conception of Hamartia includes all the three meanings mentioned above, which in English cannot be covered by a
single term.”

Hamartia is an error, or a series of errors, “whether morally culpable or


not,” committed by an otherwise noble person, and these errors derive
him to his doom. The tragic irony lies in the fact that hero may err
mistakenly without any evil intention, yet he is doomed no less than
immorals who sin consciously. He has Hamartia and as a result his very
virtues hurry him to his ruin. Says Butcher: “Othello in the modern drama, Oedipus in
the ancient, are the two most conspicuous examples of ruin wrought by character, noble indeed, but not without
defects, acting in the dark and, as it seemed, for the best.”

Aristotle lays down another qualification for the tragic hero. He must be,
“of the number of those in the enjoyment of great reputation and
prosperity.” He must be a well-reputed individual occupying a position of
lofty eminence in society. This is so because Greed tragedy, with which
alone Aristotle was familiar, was written about a few distinguished royal
families. Aristotle considers eminence as essential for the tragic hero. But
Modern drama demonstrates that the meanest individual can also serve as
a tragic hero, and that tragedies of Sophoclean grandeur can be enacted
even in remote country solitudes.

However, Aristotle’s dictum is quite justified on the principle that, “higher


the state, the greater the fall that follows,” or because heavens
themselves blaze forth the death of princes, while the death of a beggar
passes unnoticed. But it should be remembered that Aristotle nowhere says
that the hero should be a king or at least royally descended. They were
the Renaissance critics who distorted Aristotle and made the qualification
more rigid and narrow.

You might also like