Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 5

Buffalo Law Review

Volume 11 | Number 2 Article 11

1-1-1962

Freedom and the Law. By Bruno Leoni.


Arthur S. Miller
The National Law Center of The George Washington University

Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.buffalo.edu/buffalolawreview


Part of the Law and Society Commons

Recommended Citation
Arthur S. Miller, Freedom and the Law. By Bruno Leoni., 11 Buff. L. Rev. 424 (1962).
Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.buffalo.edu/buffalolawreview/vol11/iss2/11

This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at Digital Commons @ University at Buffalo School of Law. It has
been accepted for inclusion in Buffalo Law Review by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ University at Buffalo School of Law. For more
information, please contact [email protected].
BOOK REVIEW
FREEDOM AND THE LAW. By Bruno Leoni. Princeton, New Jersey: D. Van
Nostrand Company, Inc., 1961. Pp. 204. $6.00.
An Italian lawyer has written a book which exemplifies in classic form
the operation of "the fallacy of 19th-centuryism." That is the fallacy-all too
evident today, as witness, for example, the activities of those political groups
often called the "Far Right"--which is manifested by the notion that institu-
tions suitable for one period in history can be resurrected, dusted off, and made
viable for a later period in which the social conditions are fundamentally
different.' Despite the numerous adherents to that sort of "thinking," its faulty
nature would seem, on reflection, to be obvious. Perhaps the tenacity with
which some hold to it may indicate that it serves in part to satisfy deep-felt
psychological yearings-for certainty, for a "golden age," for simpler times-
during an era of rapid, even cataclysmic social change. Technological change,
which is creating a "new society," 2 manages to drive some back into a search
for the womb.
Bruno Leoni proposes that the sphere of legislation be substantially re-
stricted to limits defined by the "golden rule." He would replace law as
legislation with a system of law as something discovered and applied by judges
independently of the will of the official authority and expressing a "common
will." In short, he calls for a return to a "common law" system of juris-
prudence. Since this is seriously propounded by a person who is Professor of
Legal Theory and the Theory of the State at the University of Pavia, Chair-
man of the Faculty of Political Science, Director of the Institute of Political
Science, editor of the quarterly review Ii Politico, President of the Center of
Methodological Studies in Turin, a practicing lawyer, a contributing columnist
to the Italian financial newspaper 24 ore, and a sometime Distinguished Visiting
Professor at the Thomas Jefferson Center for Studies in Political Economy at
the University of Virginia, the book deserves attention. The danger of legis-
lation and of identifying law-creation with the legislative process, to Leoni,
is that it leads ineluctably to the diminution of individual freedom. Perhaps
the flavor of his message may be derived from the following brief quotes:
The paradoxical situation of our times is that we are governed by
men, not, as the classical Aristotelian theory would
3
contend, because
we are not governed by laws, but because we are.
My earnest suggestion is that those who value individual freedom
1. For a statement of this fallacy in a different context, see Miller, Foreign Trade
and the "Security State": A Study in Conflicting National Policies, 7 J. Pub. L. 37,
91 n. 233 (1958).
2. Compare Carr, The New Society (1951) with Seidenberg, Anatomy of the
Future (1961) and Drucker, The New Society (1950).
3. P. 9.
BOOK REVIEW

should reassess the place of the individual within the legal system as
a whole. 4
...A legal system centered on legislation resembles in its turn . . .
a centralized economy in which all the relevant decisions are made by
a handful of directors, whose knowledge of the whole situation is
fatally limited and whose5 respect, if any, for the people's wishes is
subject to that limitation.
Unless I am wrong, there is more than an analogy between the market
economy and a judiciary or lawyers' law, just as there is much more
than an analogy between a planned economy and legislation.,
The problem of our time . . seems to be . . . that of getting rid
of a host of harmful or at least useless rules because
7 of a tremendous
glut and, so to say, an indigestible surfeit of them.
The Leoni prescription, thus, is the analog of that school of current
economic thought which travels under the banner of "neo-liberalism." 8 Since
a number of practitioners of this discipline are located there, perhaps this
could be termed the University of Chicago School of Economic Liberalism.
Freedom and the Law is, in that connection, one of a series-the William
Volker Fund Series in the Humane Studies-one of the other volumes of which
having been written by the well-known neo-liberal, Ludwig von Mises.
In the somewhat larger context, then, of the neo-liberal posture, what might
be said about Bruno Leoni's proposal? The brief compass of a book review
permits only the listing of several remarks in somewhat dogmatic form. These
include the following:
1. "Neo-liberalism" is an example of how far the human mind can go
in seriously proposing public policies without reference to the underlying
social structure. Leoni's prescription has some limited interest as an exhor-
tation. But since it does not take into consideration either the fact that policy
cannot be divorced from the social milieu of the era or the fact that policy
is a continuing process and not something that can spring Minerva-like into
full bloom, it does not go beyond its hortatory nature.
2. Leoni takes the common-law system as he believes it was historically
and equates it with the maximization of human freedom. But it is pertinent
to ask: Freedom for whom? We have long known that "necessitous men are
not free men." During the 19th century-the heyday of the common law-the
majority of men were necessitous.
3. Human affairs are moving in the direction of greater and greater organ-
ization; 9 the principle of organization seems to be all-pervasive. Technology
4. Ibid.
5. Pp. 21-22.
6. P. 22.
7. P. 23.
8. See Hanslowe, Neo-liberalism: An Analysis and Proposed Application, 9 J. Pub.
L. 96 (1960).
9. See Seidenberg, Post-Historic Man (1960); Boulding, The Organizational Revo-
lution (1953).
BUFFALO LAW REVIEW

is giving added impetus to that trend. Just as the industrial revolution spelled
the doom of the historical common-law system, so too is the present-day scien-
tific revolution creating new imperatives making it unlikely at best that any
reversion such as Leoni advocates will come about. The implication of tech-
nology is the planned society-planning in fact is made necessary by tech-
nology'°--and the thought of judges doing that planning is ludicrous.
4. To expect courts to save us from our follies is, as Learned Hand re-
minded us three decades ago," fatuous. Judges are not supermen and are not
likely to have that type of expertise so greatly needed in a technological society.
5. There is a role for the courts, and particularly for the United States
Supreme Court, but it is not that of creating a body of law in the sense of a
consistent corpus of principle. (The decisions of administrators are far more
important in this respect-more important in the number of decisions and
more important in the intrinsic significance of decisions-than are those of
judges. True today, when the "administrative state" is coming into full swing,
it is likely to be even more so in the future.) The historical task of courts
is being changed. It is not yet clear just what it will be in a full-blown tech-
nological state. Possibly the United States Supreme Court will find a place
as the "national conscience" of the people, setting norms toward which the
2
people might strive.'
6. It is difficult to understand how anyone can write a book about freedom
and law in these days and make no reference to the threat of war or the
possibility of thermonuclear holocaust or to the population explosion so evident
in the poor nations (those which are now euphemistically called "less devel-
oped"). The vacuum in which Leoni makes his prescription is almost complete;
it is entirely devoid of reference to most of the hurricane winds of change and
turmoil that are sweeping the world today.' 3
I do not mean to denigrate what appears to be a serious proposition. Much
of what Leoni says no doubt makes sense. Certainly his call for a higher degree
of human freedom should find a ready response. But the problem of freedom
in the modern era is far more complex than he believes' 4 and it is not likely
that books such as his do much to further the cause of human liberty. The
talents of the neo-liberals could well be turned to more useful and meaningful
tasks, such as analysis and explication of means by which the social conditions
could be established which would permit the flowering of freedom throughout

10. See Mayo, The New Technology and National Goals: Some Implications for
Legal-Policy Decision Making, 37 Notre Dame Law. 33 (1961).
11. See Hand, The Contribution of an Independent Judiciary, in Hand, The Spirit
of Liberty 181 (Dilliard ed. 1952).
12. Cf. Miller, An Affirmative Thrust to Due Process of Law?, 30 Geo. Wash. L.
Rev. - (1962).
13. See, e.g., Ward, The Rich Nations and the Poor Nations (1962).
14. Leoni might well read Handlin & Handlin, The Dimensions of Liberty (1961);
Arendt, Between Past and Future (1961); Bay, The Structure of Freedom (1958).
426
BOOK REVIEW

the world. Exercises such as Freedom and the Law add little to our under-
standing and offer nothing to the fuller realization of the goal of freedom.
ARTHuR S. MILLER
Professor of Law
The National Law Center of
The George Washington University

You might also like