Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 18

Why the Five Ways?

Aquinas’s Avicennian Insight into the Problem of Unity in


the Aristotelian Metaphysics and Sacra Doctrina
Daniel D. De Haan

Abstract: This paper will argue that the order and the unity of St. Thomas Aquinas’s
five ways can be elucidated through a consideration of St. Thomas’s appropria-
tion of an Avicennian insight that he used to order and unify the wisdom of the
Aristotelian and Abrahamic philosophical traditions towards the existence of God.
I will begin with a central aporia from Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Aristotle says that
the science of first philosophy has three different theoretical vectors: ontology,
aitiology, and theology. But how can all three be united into a single Aristotelian
science? In his Metaphysics of the Healing, Avicenna resolved the impasse by tak-
ing the ontological vector as the subject of metaphysics. He then integrated the
question of the four first causes into the penultimate stage of his demonstration
for the existence of God, thereby placing aitiological and theological questions
among the ultimate concerns of a unified Aristotelian metaphysics. In the five
ways, St. Thomas integrated Avicenna’s Aristotelian search for the first four causes
into the last four of his five ways, by showing that each of the four aitiological
orders terminate in an ultimate first cause that we call God. Finally, by appending
the proof from the Physics to the beginning of the five ways, St. Thomas was able
to show that the ultimate aim of both natural philosophy and metaphysics is the
divine first principle, which is the beginning and subject of sacra doctrina.

T
he Abrahamic philosophical tradition has proposed a variety of ways
to demonstrate the existence of God. With so many ways to choose
from, why did Saint Thomas Aquinas select the five ways to be the
philosophical cornerstone of his Summa theologiae? The proper interpretation of the
five ways remains an ongoing debate. Though any explanation ultimately must be
theological,1 Brother Thomas does acknowledge that the five ways are praeambula
fidei taken from philosophy, which have been assimilated into his theological sci-
ence.2 If this is the case, then perhaps a partial explanation for these five ways can

©
2013, Proceedings of the ACPA, Vol. 86 pp. 141–158
doi: 10.5840/acpaproc20138612
142 Philosophy in the Abrahamic Traditions

be found through exploring their native place within Aquinas’s natural philosophy
and metaphysics.
While most interpretations tend to examine each of the five ways individually,
I offer here a complementary approach that interprets the unity of the five ways as
a complete whole. For the sake of spatial considerations, however, I will focus my
attention on the last four ways. Unfortunately, this way of proceeding forces me—in
this study—to take for granted that the first way is a theological hybrid of the way
from the Physics, that is, it begins in natural philosophy and ends in metaphysical
theology. I will argue that the remaining four of the five ways should be regarded as
a fourfold unit aimed at a sapiential answer to the aitiological concerns of Aristotle’s
Metaphysics. The Metaphysics poses a problem for all its would-be commentators:
how can the science of the ultimate first four causes be reconciled with an onto-
logical science of being qua being and a theological science of divine causes? This
study contends that the five ways should be understood, first, as central to Aquinas’s
philosophical solution to the problem of unity in the Aristotelian metaphysics, and,
second, as illustrating the unity and the subordination of the philosophical sciences’
natural knowledge of God to the science of sacra doctrina.
To defend this proposal I must hazard a speculative reconstruction of Aquinas’s
metaphysical science. But, unlike most overtly Aristotelian reconstructions of a
“Thomistic” metaphysics, I will follow Aquinas’s own Avicennian suggestions
concerning the subject, principles, and ultimate objects of inquiry proper to the
science of metaphysics.3 In other words, my reconstruction of Aquinas’s metaphysics
follows the model of Avicenna’s own scientific presentation of Peripatetic first
philosophy in the Metaphysics of the Healing, in contrast to many other reconstruc-
tions that adopt as their model those collated logoi by Aristotle, which came to be
called Metaphysics. Let us now turn our attention to the problem of unity within
Aristotle’s Metaphysics.

Aristotle and the Unity of Metaphysics’


Ontological, Aitiological, Theological Aims
The ordered collection of logoi by Aristotle that bears the title Metaphysics have
confronted some of the greatest philosophers with innumerable questions, puzzles,
and seemingly irresolvable difficulties. Throughout this recondite collation of logoi,
Aristotle patiently addresses problems within the framework of a scientific study of
being; however, the coherence and unity of the doctrines found within these dif-
ferent treatises remains less than perspicuous.4 A central difficulty is found in the
fact that Aristotle’s many proposals for a unified metaphysical science seem to be
fundamentally problematic. Aristotle proposes at least three apparently incompatible
trajectories for the study of being: the aitiological, ontological, and theological. We
are told that first philosophy is wisdom, because it is a science of first principles and
causes,5 but Aristotle also says that the study of being qua being is concerned with
the most universal knowledge and so it is not like those many particular sciences;
rather, it is a universal science of being.6 Third, the study of being is also called a
Why the Five Ways? 143

divine science, a theology, because God is thought to be one of the ultimate causes
and principles, and, above all, it seems that God would possess such a science.7 Now
any two of these approaches might be reconcilable, but given all three, there is no
clear prima facie answer that reveals how they can be unified within the scope of a
single science. If metaphysics is a universal science because its subject is universal
being, then it becomes unclear how its subject could also be separate substances
or theological beings, since these are particular kinds of beings. But if the ultimate
causes or divine beings are the subject of metaphysics, how can first philosophy be
called a universal science of being in contrast to all those particular sciences of being?8
The prevailing answer of Aristotle’s early Greek commentators was to charac-
terize the Aristotelian metaphysics as a theology, and that its claims to a universal
science of being qua being are justified because theological beings are the first universal
eternal principles, and so the universal causes of all other beings.9 Consequently,
because the divine beings are separate substances, it turns out that the Aristotelian
Metaphysics is principally a theological ousiology.10 On this interpretation, the on-
tological trajectory is elided into or sublimated within the trajectory of Aristotle’s
theological ousiology.11
Even if we grant this theological interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, one
still might wonder if first philosophy can achieve an unqualified unity. It remains
obscure how the study of the ultimate causes in this divine science presents a way to
God. Does the ultimate trajectory of Aristotle’s metaphysical aitiology synchronize
with the trajectory of its central task as a metaphysical theology? Since the Metaphys-
ics is called a divine science, and Aristotle has identified scientific knowledge with
the knowledge of causes,12 it seems reasonable to suppose that the study of ultimate
first causes will line up perfectly with the theological character of first philosophy.13
The study of the first causes should provide us with knowledge of the divine eternal
causes, thereby certifying the scientific character of metaphysics as a divine science.
What are the causes that provide us with knowledge of divine beings?
It is well known that Aristotle distinguishes four causes: material, formal,
moving, and final. Indeed book Α of the Metaphysics is dedicated to reiterating, as
metaphysical principles, the four causes that were established in the Physics. It was
the task of the natural philosophy of the Physics to introduce the four causes, but it
belongs to the aitiological task of metaphysics to address the question of the ultimate
first causes and to establish that all four orders of causality are finite. This aitiological
endeavor is addressed in Metaphysics α 2, which opens with the claim that “clearly
there is some principle (αρχή τις), and the causes of things are not infinite.”14 If we
read α 2 as continuous with α 1—which contains such contentions as the claim
that the science of truth is the science of causes, and that the most true beings are
the unchanging causes of all inferior beings and their truth—then we are likely to
conclude that α 2’s arguments for the impossibility of an infinite regress in each order
of causality also aim to show that eternal beings exist and that they are the causes of
being and truth. Said otherwise, “After having identified the science of truth with
the science of causes, Aristotle proceeds to demonstrate that first causes exist. He
144 Philosophy in the Abrahamic Traditions

shows that in the lines of material, formal, efficient, and final causality there must
always be a first uncaused cause, both in kind and number.”15
Questions about the continuity among the chapters of α as well as its place
within the Metaphysics present any interpretation with a number of difficulties that
I cannot address here.16 Nevertheless, there are a few problems we must take up.
First, if Aristotle has sought to establish a first uncaused cause in each of the four
lines of causality, there is no explicit mention of divine beings to be found in α 2.
Second, it is not clear whether Aristotle sought to establish four different kinds of
uncaused causes or some uncaused and eternal principles that are the first causes
of all four orders of causality.17 The question we must ask is: do all four causes lead
us to some ultimate first causes that can be identified with divine beings? In other
words, do all four causes provide us with four distinct ways to the existence of, at
least, one divine first principle?
While the conclusions of Metaphysics α remain obscure, the arguments for the
immovable first mover from the Physics and the divine beings from Metaphysics Λ
give us reason to believe Aristotle thought that we can arrive at the existence of a
divine being through moving and final causes. But do these two ways to separate
substances completely unite Aristotle’s aitiological proposal to follow the four orders
of causality to their ultimate divine first causes? In Metaphysics Λ, Aristotle does
identify the first ultimate final causes with the divine eternal separate substances,18
but the way to the unmoved mover from the Physics has been interpreted variously
as a way from the movement of agent causality and as from final causality. Scholars
also disagree about its conclusion; does it reach a non-divine, yet animated, cosmic
first principle or a divine first principle? If both texts are given the most robust in-
terpretations available, it seems that Aristotle might be able to integrate moving and
formal causality into the causality of some ultimate divine final cause.19 But even if
we grant this tenuous solution, it remains unclear exactly how Aristotelian material
causality could be derived from the causality of divine beings. In other words, how
could the first, uncaused, eternal material cause from Metaphysics α 2 be anything
other than prime matter, which is not divine? And, if it is prime matter, how can it
be reduced to or accounted for by any other line of causality? Matter is, of course,
subordinated to formal act, but this does not account for its eternal and ungener-
ated existence.20 Material causality remains an obstacle to any attempts to establish
the unity of the aitiological and theological trajectories of Aristotle’s metaphysical
divine science.

In short, because the God of Aristotle is one of the causes and one of the
principles of all things, but not the cause nor the principle of all things,
there remains in the Aristotelian domain of being something which the
God of Aristotle does not account for, which is matter, and for this reason
the metaphysics of Aristotle cannot be reduced to unqualified unity.21

Aristotle might be able to defend the position that the divine eternal principles are
the first agent and formal-cum-final causes, but material causality remains an outlier
Why the Five Ways? 145

and a serious lacuna within the Metaphysics. Hence, not all of the first causes of Aris-
totle’s metaphysical aitiology can be derived from or identified with the divine causes
established in his metaphysical theology. In the end, it is not clear how Aristotle’s
metaphysical theology can unite its aitiological study of the four first causes of be-
ing with separate divine beings. This was one among a number of maladies that the
Peripatetic Healing of Avicenna sought to remedy. But to understand properly how
his Metaphysics of the Healing administered this cure, we first must grasp Avicenna’s
diagnosis of the ailment.

Avicenna: Four First Causes and


One Efficient Way to God’s Existence
The Metaphysics of the Healing proposes to be a scientific study of being qua
being after the manner of a Peripatetic science.22 But the work is no mere commentary
on Aristotle’s Metaphysics. In fact, Avicenna intrepidly aims to improve the science of
Aristotle by deploying his own philosophical insights into the necessity of existence
found in all beings, and by establishing a scientific Aristotelian metaphysics that
follows the scientific directives set forth in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics.
The first ambiguity of Aristotle’s Metaphysics that Avicenna aims to resolve
concerns the problem: what is the subject of metaphysics? Having suffered years of
perplexity about this question in his teenage years, the precocious Avicenna finally
discovered the proper prescription in Al-Fārābī’s Intentions of the Philosopher. This
work made clear to the adolescent Avicenna that the subject of metaphysics is neither
the ultimate causes nor God, but is being as being, that is, being in general, and
that the first causes and God are the ultimate objects of metaphysical inquiry. The
significance of this point should not be overlooked, for it provides the cornerstone
of Avicenna’s metaphysics and allowed him to bring into scientific unity the whole
of Peripatetic first philosophy. The ontological trajectory of the Metaphysics is re-
defined by Avicenna and is taken as the subject of metaphysics, and the aitiological
and theological vectors are placed at the end of metaphysics as its ultimate objects
of inquiry.23 It is in Avicenna’s detailed account of the aitiological and theological
approaches’ rendezvous that will provide us with sufficient signals for understanding
why Aquinas chose his five ways.
After establishing the subject and principles in book one of his metaphysics,
Avicenna sets out to study the many objects of inquiry which follow upon being
as being as so many quasi-species and quasi-properties of being.24 By so doing, he
introduces a regimented order into the topics taken up by Aristotle’s demonstrative
metaphysical science of being as being. He begins with substance and moves on to
treat accidents, the one and the many, act and potency, universals, causality, and also
the errors of the Platonists. By the time we arrive at book eight of the Metaphysics of
the Healing, Avicenna has established numerous demonstrations concerning what
follows upon being, yet nothing explicitly has been demonstrated with respect to the
ultimate causes of being, or with respect to the existence of God. Book eight begins,
“Now that we have arrived at this stage in our book, it behooves us to conclude it
146 Philosophy in the Abrahamic Traditions

with [the question] of the knowledge of the First Principle of all existences.”25 But
before demonstrating the existence of God, Avicenna must resolve the aitiological
lacuna of Aristotle’s Metaphysics.

The first thing we ought to do in this is to show that the causes are in all
respects finite, that in each of their classes there is a first principle, that
the principle of all of them is one, that He differs from all [other] beings,
and that He alone is the necessary existence, and that, in the case of every
[other] being, the beginning of its existence is from Him.26

Rather than wedging the treatment of the impossibility of an infinite regress into
the beginning of his metaphysical science, Avicenna explicitly redistributes Meta-
physics α’s treatment of the finitude of the four causes into the initial stages of his
demonstration for the existence of God. But whereas the unity of Aristotle’s aitiology
and theology remained schismatic, or at least ambiguous, Avicenna provides a very
precise answer to the question of how the first four causes can all be connected to
the causality of the divine being. After showing that there must be a first efficient
cause of existence, as well as first material, formal, and final causes, Avicenna takes
up the Aristotelian aporia and provides an answer, which despite its precision, is
astonishingly brief.

If we say [that something is] a first efficient principle—rather, a first


absolute principle—then it must necessarily be one. If, however, we
say [it is] a first elemental principle and a first formal principle and the
like, [such a principle] would not have the same necessity of being one
as the necessity of this in the necessary existence. [This is] because none
of [these causes] would be a first absolute cause because the necessary
existence is one and has the status of the efficient principle. Hence the
one, the necessary existence, would also be a cause of these first [causes].27

Nothing could be more Avicennian than to solve a metaphysical difficulty by ap-


pealing to his favorite primordial metaphysical principle “the necessary.” What is
significant for the purposes of this study is the way Avicenna has integrated the
first and ultimate four Aristotelian causes into his metaphysical treatment of God’s
existence. Avicenna spends the first part of book eight demonstrating that all four
lines of causality are finite and terminate in a first cause—just as Aristotle had done
in Metaphysics α 2. He then unites his metaphysical study of the ultimate causes with
his demonstration for the existence of the divine being by identifying the first efficient
cause of existence with God, the one necessary existence through itself.28 The chief
unifying maneuver occurs next. Because God is the first efficient cause of existence,
this means that God causes the existence of the first causes in the other orders of
final, formal, and material causality. Hence, Avicenna is able to channel together
both the aitiological and theological currents of his metaphysics by identifying the
one divine being with the first efficient cause, an identification that even allows him
to mop up the first material cause left out to dry by Aristotle’s theological ousiology.
Why the Five Ways? 147

We should not allow the efficiency of Avicenna’s argument to confuse us


about what he has and has not accomplished. First, despite the misinterpretations
of some readers of Avicenna, we must recognize that there is no demonstration for
the existence of God by way of possibility and necessity anywhere in the Metaphysics
of the Healing.29 Rather, Avicenna’s approach to the existence of God requires that
we first demonstrate the finitude of the four causal orders,30 then show that God is
the first efficient cause of existence, and then, finally, we must establish that God,
the first efficient cause, is the ultimate cause of the existence of the first material,
formal, and final causes.
In short, Avicenna succeeds in uniting the ontological subject of his meta-
physical science with the aitiological and theological objects of inquiry through
his innovative integration of the aitiological vector into the early stages of his dem-
onstration for the existence of God. Said otherwise, the culmination of Avicenna’s
ontology of possible existences shifts to address certain ultimate aitiological concerns
that all terminate in the existence of a first efficient cause, which is God, whose
very exalted name announces the arrival of Avicenna’s metaphysical theology. As
far as solutions to the problem of unqualified unity in Aristotelian metaphysics go,
Avicenna’s theological integration of the four first causes might seem like a radical
solution, yet, as we will see, the five ways of Thomas Aquinas went one step further.

Thomas Aquinas: Four First Causes within


the Five Ways to God’s Existence
Brother Thomas was aware of the fact that the Abrahamic philosophical tradi-
tion contained a multitude of ways that all promised to establish the existence of God.
In fact, Aquinas had argued for the existence of God in many different settings and
employed a number of different ways to do so.31 What we want to know is why he
chose the five ways of the Summa theologiae to be among the philosophical praeambula
fidei of his sacred theology? Answers to this question are legion. To cut through the
ranks, we turn again to the problem that beset the unity of the Metaphysics.
Following Avicenna, Aquinas contends that the subject of metaphysics is neither
God nor the ultimate causes, but is being as being, or common being. “Consequently,
[divine beings] are the objects of the science that investigates what is common to
all beings which has for its subject being as being.”32 Philosophical theology is the
fruition of the scientific wisdom called metaphysics. Yet, for Brother Thomas, the
philosophical way to knowledge of God is not exclusive, for God also has revealed
Himself to mankind so that, through faith, we have a way to consider divine things
in themselves, and not just as the principles of other beings.

Accordingly, there are two kinds of theology or divine science. There


is one that treats of divine things, not as the subject of the science but
as the principles of the subject. This is the kind of theology pursued by
philosophers and that is also called metaphysics. There is another theol-
ogy . . . taught in Sacred Scripture.33
148 Philosophy in the Abrahamic Traditions

Whereas metaphysics or philosophical theology studies common being as its subject


and separate divine beings as the ultimate principles of its subject, the theology of
Sacred Scripture or sacra doctrina studies separate divine beings as its subject. So how
does this division help us to understand the five ways found in the Summa theologiae?
We must first recognize that, even though the Summa theologiae takes it as a
matter of faith that God exists and is the subject of sacred theology, the rational
arguments found in the philosophical theology of metaphysics are not irrelevant to
sacred theology. A higher science, like sacred theology, whose subject is God, can
make use of the principles, demonstrations, and conclusions found in any lower
science, such as metaphysics, whose cause and ultimate object of inquiry is God.34
In ST I.2.2 ad 1m, Aquinas acknowledges that the five ways, like other preambles
to the articles of faith, are doctrines taken from the philosophical sciences that are
assimilated into sacred theology, just as faith and grace presuppose the knowledge
and nature they perfect. Now it belongs to the philosophical science of metaphysics
to establish the first ultimate causes and the existence of God. But where exactly do
the demonstrations for God’s existence fit within Aquinas’s metaphysics?
I suggested earlier that attempts to erect St. Thomas’s metaphysical science
should not use the loosely bound order of Aristotle’s Metaphysics as a model, but
instead should base their reconstructions on the systematic metaphysical science
found in Avicenna’s Metaphysics of the Healing. We can now provide a number of
reasons that fortify this suggestion. First, there is no clear model set forth in Aristotle’s
Metaphysics. In fact, it leaves unresolved the very problems that the different answers
of Avicenna and Averroes intended to resolve. Second, it is because of these ambigui-
ties in the Metaphysics that, despite being very different interpretations of the same
work, the distinct positions of Avicenna and Averroes specified for scholastics two
alternative models of the subject, principles, and order of Aristotelian metaphysics.
Third, whenever Aquinas actually compares various Aristotelian interpretations of
Aristotelian metaphysics, his own position on the subject, principles, and objects
of metaphysical inquiry is always thoroughly Avicennian.35 Given these historical
facts, we have good reasons for following St. Thomas and looking to Avicenna as a
model for Aquinas’s Aristotelian metaphysics, instead of trying to use Aristotle to
answer questions for St. Thomas that Aristotle himself neither asked nor answered.
Now, no less than Avicenna, St. Thomas saw the need to unite the metaphysi-
cal inquiry of ultimate causes with the existence of God as the culminating goal of
metaphysics. We already have seen that Avicenna’s solution consisted in establishing
that there are four first causes, that God should be identified with the first efficient
cause, and, finally, that God is the first efficient cause of the existence of the lesser
first causes. As a philosopher, Aquinas simply could adopt the answer that Avicenna
gives to the aporia of Aristotle’s Metaphysics; however, this would not settle the greater
difficulties that confront Brother Thomas the theologian. To resolve the problem
of unity in the ontological, aitiological, and theological trajectories of metaphysics
does not complete the further task of sacred theology to unite all the philosophical
sciences under the ultimate end of God Himself, the subject of sacred theology.
How did St. Thomas accomplish such an enterprise?
Why the Five Ways? 149

I submit that the five ways of St. Thomas provide the cornerstone to this ambi-
tious theological endeavor of the Summa theologiae. In short, not only do the five ways
resolve the aporetic tensions of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, but they also provide a way
for sublimating the ultimate trajectories of natural philosophy and metaphysics into
the higher ends of sacred theology. Let us explicate these two points in succession.
If we examine the last four of the five ways within their native metaphysical
context, a striking resemblance emerges between the argumentative goals of these
four ways with the four causes of Aristotle and the attempts of Metaphysics α 2 and
Metaphysics of the Healing VIII.1–3 to establish a first in each of the four lines of
causality. This is why the point of departure for the last four of the five ways is taken
from the effects of efficient, material, formal, and final causality. In the last four ways,
Aquinas shows that the ultimate trajectory of each of the four orders of causality must
culminate in a first uncaused cause. And, just as in Avicenna, St. Thomas’s account
reveals that the aitiological pursuit of the four ultimate causes can be integrated into
the theological approach to God’s existence, an integration that also resolves the
aporia of unity in the Aristotelian metaphysics. Yet, a salient difference between the
solutions of Avicenna and Aquinas should not be overlooked. For Avicenna, it was
only the first efficient cause that was identified with God. The first material, formal,
and final causes were all caused by the absolutely first efficient cause, i.e., God. In
the five ways Aquinas goes beyond Avicenna and uncovers a way to show how each
of the four orders of causality provide distinct ways, not just to a first cause, but also
to a first uncaused transcendent cause that is identified with God Himself.
But there still is one more respect in which Aquinas goes beyond Avicenna.
Contrary to Avicenna, St. Thomas defends the position that the argument from
motion in the Physics—once properly theologized by a metaphysical injection of act
and potency—is able to terminate in a first principle that is identified with God.36
In short, even though the five ways share a common trajectory as arguments for the
existence of God, they, in fact, do commence with five different points of departure,
that, by five different routes, ultimately terminate in a first principle that is identi-
fied with God. “Each of the five ways truly ends up with the existence of a being
such that the name ‘God’ cannot be denied to it, whatever else the name ought to
signify. The five ways are, accordingly, at one and the same time both independent
and complementary.”37
More significantly, this point helps us to see the way in which the subject and
principles studied in both natural philosophy and metaphysics ultimately provide
us with ways to the existence of God that can be assimilated into sacred theology.38
The five ways provide not only a solution to the problem of unity in metaphysics,
but they also serve as the opening gambit to Aquinas’s theological science, for the
five ways make perspicuous that the ultimate conclusions of natural philosophy and
metaphysics are oriented to the knowledge of God, the subject of sacred theology.
And because the ultimate conclusions of the philosophical sciences are directed
towards the subject of sacred theology, there can be no objection to the gratuitous
perfection and integration of their doctrines into the higher science of sacred theol-
ogy as preambles of faith.39
150 Philosophy in the Abrahamic Traditions

Finally, and for the sake of our more suspicious readers, let us first point out
that these apparently speculative connections between the five ways and the first
causes of the four orders of causality is made clear in Aquinas’s later treatment of
God and creation. Because “God is the efficient, the exemplar and the final cause
of all things, and primary matter is from Him, it follows that the first principle
of all things is only one in reality.”40 Questions two and forty-four of the Summa
theologiae simply articulate two different directions on the same path; the former
brings us from creation to God, while the latter convey us from God to creation.
In short, the four causes of the five ways and the creation of the causes and effects
within each of the four orders of causality serve as complementary bookends to the
whole of Aquinas’s treatment of God as one, triune creator.41
Second, if our reader is still doubtful about the Avicennian connections made
above, I ask that he consider the following facts. Not only does the whole of question
two of the Summa theologiae exhibit an Avicennian influence, but even St. Thomas’s
approach to the divine essence in questions three through six follow the exact same
order of topics set out in the Vizier’s metaphysical theology. After demonstrating
God’s existence, Aquinas, like Avicenna, goes on to demonstrate that God is simple,
that as pure existence God is pure perfection, and because goodness in general is
connected with perfection and existence, God must be goodness itself as He is
existence and perfection in itself.42 In short, it is quite clear that Avicenna provided
the model for the set of questions St. Thomas selected to treat at the beginning of
the Summa theologiae.

Thomas Aquinas:
Intrinsic and Extrinsic Material and Formal Causes
Let us conclude this all too cursory investigation with an additional clarification
of how the five ways bear upon the problem of the unity within Aristotle’s Metaphys-
ics. I have argued that Aquinas looks to the aitiological concerns of metaphysics with
the four ultimate causes as his point of departure for the second through the fifth of
the five ways. Most readers of St. Thomas agree that the second, fourth, and fifth
ways bear a clear resemblance or connection to efficient causality, formal or exemplar
causality, and final causality, respectively.43 But what justification is there for believ-
ing that the third way, from possibility and necessity, presents an argument to God’s
existence on the basis of a first cause in the order of material causality? In order to
answer this question, I must begin with the point of departure of the fourth way.
A distinguishing characteristic of St. Thomas’s arguments for God’s existence
is that they all advance from the extrinsic causes of some effect to God’s existence as
first cause. Unlike the extrinsic causality of efficient and final causes, material and
formal causes are both intrinsic causes inasmuch as their combined causality results
in the effect that is a composite hylomorphic substance. Formal causes, however,
can be considered in two ways, as intrinsic or extrinsic causes. The ultimate or first
intrinsic formal causes are the substantial forms of substances, but these intrinsic
first causes are effects with respect to the extrinsic formal causes that they imitate.
Why the Five Ways? 151

Such extrinsic formal causes are also known as exemplar causes, and the first ul-
timate exemplar cause is God.44 Instead of rearticulating the well-known doctrine
that the first intrinsic formal cause of all substances is its substantial form, the point
of departure of the fourth way simply assumes this. This assumption allows St.
Thomas to begin with an extrinsic consideration of the formal effects of substances
inasmuch as they are formally definite or finite perfections that imitate some infinite
exemplary perfection. In short, it is on the basis of the causal connection between
intrinsic formal perfections and extrinsic exemplar causality that allows St. Thomas
to follow the order of finite formal causes to the first exemplar cause, which is God.
The third way begins by supposing a similar shift from an intrinsic to an
extrinsic consideration of material causality. And, like in the fourth way, the third
way assumes that we are familiar with the Aristotelian doctrine that prime matter
is the first intrinsic material cause. St. Thomas is quite sympathetic to difficulties
concerning the doctrine of prime matter. After all, it did take philosophers a long
time to discover that God is the first extrinsic cause of the existence of prime mat-
ter.45 Despite such difficulties, it nevertheless remains the case that it is manifestly
stupid to hold that God Himself is prime matter.46 This being so, how does prime
matter bring us to God as the ultimate extrinsic cause of the first intrinsic material
cause? For St. Thomas, all hylomorphic substances are composed with prime matter,
and because of this composition with the first intrinsic material cause all physical
beings have the potentiality to corrupt. Consequently, all hylomorphic substances
are mere possible existents, which is the extrinsic effect entailed by being a thing
composed with the first intrinsic material cause. Now an extrinsic causal explanation
is needed once we recognize that an extrinsic consideration of material substances
reveals that they are all possible existents. In short, the first intrinsic material cause
compels us to look for an extrinsic cause that accounts for all possible existents, that
is, all beings composed of prime matter. And this is precisely what is assumed in
the third way’s introductory observation that it is possible for some beings to exist
or not to exist. In short, possible existents generate and corrupt.
There is also compelling textual evidence supporting our contention that pos-
sible existents signal material causality for St. Thomas. It is undoubtedly the case that
the structure of the third way was influenced by the argument of the Abrahamic phi-
losopher, Moses Maimonides. Nevertheless, we should not overlook the third way’s
connection with Aquinas’s earlier critique of the Avicennian doctrine of possibility,
and the presentation of his own view. In De potentia 5.3, Aquinas rejects Avicenna’s
position that locates possibility for nonexistence in all quiddities or common natures
other than God, who alone is necessary existence through himself. Aquinas claims
to follow the account of Averroes instead, and situates the principle of possibility
for nonexistence, not in the quiddity or common nature of every thing other than
God, but in those natures that include matter. This is because prime matter, the
first material cause, is pure potentiality open to alternative substantial forms, that
is, it has the potentiality to corrupt and the possibility for nonexistence. In fact, not
even materiality in general is sufficient to show that all physical beings have a passive
potentiality for corruption and nonexistence; prime matter is the essential element
152 Philosophy in the Abrahamic Traditions

required for holding that all physical beings are possible existents, i.e., possibles in
the sense of having a passive potentiality not to exist. Hence, for St. Thomas there
are beings other than God that have necessary existence by their nature, yet, unlike
God, they are not the cause of their necessary existence.47
In brief, St. Thomas clearly holds that the possibility for nonexistence is nested
within material causality. Accordingly, we have very strong textual evidence for
holding that the third way does, in fact, take its point of departure from material
causality. The third way then goes on to show that the possibility rooted in material
things ultimately demands, not only that there be necessary existents, but that there
exist a being whose necessary existence is not caused, and this is God. It is in this
somewhat circuitous way that Aquinas ultimately establishes God’s existence by start-
ing first with the order of material causality in all possible existents and ultimately
concluding with the existence of God as the first uncaused necessary existent that
is the cause of all possible existents and caused necessary existents.48
Still, one might object that there is nothing in the third way that uniquely
focuses our attention on material causality and that the efficient causality of existence
seems to play a significant role in bringing us from beings that are necessary existents
through another to a being that is necessary existence in itself. While I am willing
to concede the latter point, I think that the former claim—that material causality
is not salient to the third way—is simply false. The point of departure of the third
way is intelligible only if we concede that material causality is the distinguishing
characteristic of possible existents. Neither formal nor efficient causality distinguish
possible existents from beings that are necessary existents through another, for the
putative reason that both possible and necessary existents have form and existence.
But the one factor that indisputably distinguishes them is that all necessary exis-
tents are completely separate from prime matter, whereas all possible existents are
composed with prime matter. In short, Thomas holds that prime matter is the
fundamental distinguishing factor of all possible existents, and this is why I have
argued that material causality is the point of departure of the third way.

Conclusion
In this study, I have argued that Avicenna provided St. Thomas with a key
insight that allowed him to use the five ways to unify and order the otherwise diver-
gent aitiological and theological goals of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, as well as to unify
the ends of the philosophical sciences with the subject of sacred theology. In other
words, the five ways solve two problems of unity, one in metaphysics and a second
in sacred theology. The last four ways resolved the metaphysical problem of unity,
while all five ways were needed to answer the second problem of unity.
In evaluating an interpretation of St. Thomas, we should distinguish between
two questions: First, does it solve the philosophical or theological problem at issue?
Second, does it elucidate the intentions of St. Thomas? With respect to the former,
this interpretation of the five ways does provide an elegant solution to the problem
of unity in Aristotelian metaphysics and sacra doctrina, and in a way that is consistent
Why the Five Ways? 153

with the thought of Thomas Aquinas. Concerning the second, any attempt to il-
luminate the implicit intentions of St. Thomas is very difficult. His sapiential vision
was able to harmonize the rich resources of his intellectual forebears in the service
of ordering all of being to the first cause of being. Indeed, the order found in any
question or set of questions from the Summa theologiae reveal the real subtlety of the
Angelic Doctor’s thought. But did he intend the order of the five ways to address
the aforementioned problems? In this study, I have provided a rough sketch of the
evidence that supports the contention that St. Thomas did intend the five ways to
resolve such problems. He knew the Aristotelian problematic and Avicenna’s solu-
tion; he frequently repeated his own commitment to the Avicennian solution, and
often in the context of discussing its connections to the theological problematic.
St. Thomas also clearly intended for the conclusions of the five ways to provide the
causal foundations for our theological knowledge of God, including our knowledge
of God as creator, and just as the four causes play a prominent role in his doctrine
of creation, it is reasonable to hold that they perform a similar function in the via
affirmationis or via causalitatis of the five ways.
It belongs to wisdom to order all things and to eliminate obscurity. This study
has attempted to make clear the subtle unity, order, and purpose found within the
sapiential gambit of Saint Thomas Aquinas’s Summa theologiae. It is in the five ways
that Brother Thomas was able to establish a first divine principle that could order
the wisdom of the Aristotelian and Abrahamic philosophical traditions towards the
existence of God, the subject of sacra doctrina.

University of St. Thomas, Center for Thomistic Studies, Houston, Texas

Notes
1. See Etienne Gilson, Thomism: The Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas, translation of Le
Thomisme, sixth ed., trans., Laurence K. Shook and Armand Maurer (Toronto: PIMS, 2002),
75–83 (henceforth: Thomism).
2. See Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae I.2.2 ad1; ST II-II.2.10 ad2; In de Trinitate,
II.3.
3. See Thomas Aquinas, In I Sent., Prol., q. 1, a. 2; q. 1, a. 3, qc. 1; In de Trinitate, V.1,
ad 9; V.4; In meta., Proem. Even as late as the commentary on the Metaphysics, Aquinas still
will draw upon Avicenna to clarify or re-interpret the text of Aristotle. See, e.g., In VI Meta.,
lt. 6, n. 1165. For recent discussions on the relationship between Avicenna and Aquinas
on the subject and principles of metaphysics, see R. E. Houser, “The Real Distinction and
the Principles of Metaphysics: Avicenna and Aquinas,” in Laudemus viros gloriosos: Essays in
Honor of Armand Maurer CSB, ed. R. E. Houser (Thomistic Studies Series) (Notre Dame,
IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2007): 75–108 (henceforth: Real Distinction); idem,
“Aristotle and Two Medieval Aristotelians on the Nature of God” International Philosophical
Quarterly 51.3 (2011): 355–375; Joseph Owens, “Aquinas as Aristotelian Commentator,”
Thomas Aquinas 1274–1974: Commemorative Studies, ed. Armand Maurer (Toronto: PIMS,
1974), 213–238. John F. Wippel, “Thomas Aquinas and Avicenna on the Relationship
154 Philosophy in the Abrahamic Traditions

between First Philosophy and Other Theoretical Sciences: A Note on Thomas’s Commentary
on Boethius’s De Trinitate, Q. 5, art. 1, ad 9,” in Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas I
(Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1984), chap. 2, pp. 37–53;
idem, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic
University of America Press, 2000) (henceforth: Metaphysical Thought), 3–62 (esp. 11–22);
idem, “The Latin Avicenna as a Source for Thomas Aquinas’s Metaphysics,” in Metaphysi-
cal Themes in Thomas Aquinas II (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America
Press, 2007), chap. 2, pp. 31–65; idem, “Thomas Aquinas, Siger of Brabant, and Their Use
of Avicenna in Clarifying The Subject of Metaphysics,” in Metaphysics. The Paideia Project:
Proceedings of the 20th World Congress of Philosophy, Vol. II (1999), 15–26. On the project
of reconstructing a Thomistic metaphysics, see John F. Wippel, “Thomas Aquinas and the
Problem of Christian Philosophy” in Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas I, 22–33.
4. This paper’s interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics relies heavily upon the erudite
studies of Joseph Owens and Lloyd Gerson. See Joseph Owens, The Doctrine of Being in the
Aristotelian Metaphysics, 3rd. ed. (Toronto: PIMS, 1978) (henceforth: Doctrine of Being);
idem, Aristotle’s Gradations of Being in Metaphysics E–Z (South Bend, IN:, St. Augustine’s
Press, 2007); Lloyd P. Gerson, Aristotle and Other Platonists (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press, 2005).
5. See Aristotle, Metaphysics Α 1, 981b26–982a3; A 2, 982a5; Α 3, 983a24–25; A 10,
993a13–27; α 1, 993b20–32; Γ 2, 1003b19–22; Ε 1, 1025b3–4.
6. See Metaphysics Γ 1, 1003a20–26; Ε 1, 1025b8–11; Κ 3, 1060b31–36. See also
Α 2, 982a22–b10; Κ 3, 1061a8–18; Κ 3, 1061b3–18; Κ 4, 1061b18–34.
7. See Metaphysics Α 2 983a5–12; infra n11.
8. The aitiological approach has its own unique set of difficulties spelled out in the
aporiae of books Β and Κ. Also see infra n11.
9. See Alexander of Aphrodisias, In Metaphysics 245.33–246.6. Also see, Gerson,
Aristotle and Other Platonists, 180. It should be noted that Owens and Gerson both argue that
the universality of the Metaphysics depends on Aristotle’s doctrine that being is πρός ̀εν. See
Gerson, Aristotle and Other Platonists, 179; Owens, Doctrine of Being, xx; chap. 3.
10. See Metaphysics Ε 1, 1026a16–24.
11. After Aristotle states that first philosophy is a universal science of being qua being,
he redirects what we might take to be his prima facie ontological suggestions, and gives them
an aitiological and theological twist. See Metaphysics Γ 1, 1003a26–33; Γ 2, 1003a34–25;
Ε 1, 1026a24–36; Κ 7, 1064a29–1064b14; Owens, Doctrine of Being, chaps. 7 and 19.
12. Posterior Analytics I. 2, 71b10–72b4; Metaphysics Α 3, 983a24–983b1.
13. Metaphysics Ε 1, 1026a16–24.
14. Metaphysics α 2, 994a1–3. (Apostle, slightly modified). See Lloyd Gerson, “Causality,
Univocity, and First Philosophy in Metaphysics ii,” Ancient Philosophy 11.2 (1991): 331–349;
Joseph Owens, “The Present Status of Alpha Elatton in the Aristotelian Metaphysics” Archivfür
Geschichte der Philosophie Issue 2 (1984): 148–169.
15. Gerson, Aristotle and other Platonists, 187.
16. See supra n14. Many of the ingredients proper to later philosophical demonstrations
of God’s existence, such as those of Avicenna and Thomas Aquinas, can be found in this second
chapter of Alpha Elatton. See Amos Bertolacci, The Reception of Aristotle’s Metaphysics in
Why the Five Ways? 155

Avicenna’s Kitâb al-Shifâ’: A Milestone of Western Metaphysical Thought (Leiden-Boston: Brill,


2006), 57–58, 313–315, and 323–326; idem, “Avicenna and Averroes on The Proofs of God’s
Existence and The Subject Matter of Metaphysics,” Medioevo. Rivista di Storiadella Filosofia
Medievale 32 (2007): 61–98, esp. 78–80. Herbert Davidson, Proofs for Eternity, Creation and
the Existence of God in Medieval Islamic and Jewish Philosophy (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1987), 281–310. For a comparison of Avicenna and Aquinas, see R. E. Houser, “The
Language of Being and the Nature of God in the Aristotelian Tradition,” Proceedings of the
American Catholic Philosophical Association 84 (2010): 113–132.
17. For an account of some Neoplatonic interpretations of Metaphysics α, see Gerson,
Aristotle and Other Platonists, 180–188; see also Avicenna, Metaphysics of the Healing, trans.
and ed. Michael E. Marmura (Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press, 2005), VIII.1–3;
Aquinas, In II Meta., lt. 2–4.
18. Metaphysics Λ 7, 1072b1–13.
19. For two different speculative reconstructions of the causality attributable to divine
beings in Aristotle’s theology, see Owens, Doctrine of Being, chap. 19; Gerson, Aristotle and
Other Platonists, 200–204 ff.
20. Like form, matter is neither generated nor corrupted; rather composites are gener-
ated and corrupted, see Physics I. 9, 191b35–192b5.
21. Etienne Gilson, Being and Some Philosophers, 2nd ed. (Toronto: PIMS, 1952), 156.
22. See Michael Marmura, “Avicenna on the Division of the Sciences in the Isagoge of
his Shifā’,” Journal of the History of Arabic Science 4 (1980): 241–251; Amos Bertolacci, “The
Structure of Metaphysics Science in the Ilāhiyyāt (Divine Science) of Avicenna’s Kitāb al-Šifā’
(The Book of the Cure)” Documenti e Studi sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale 14 (2003):
227–262; Olga Lizzini, “Utility and Gratuitousness of Metaphysics: Avicenna, Ilāhiyyāt I,
3,” Quaestio 5 (2005): 307–344; Houser, Real Distinction.
23. See Avicenna, Metaphysics of The Healing, I.1–3.
24. Metaphysics of the Healing I.2.12–13 [13]. At I. 4, Avicenna presents his own “table
of contents” of the various quasi-genera and quasi-species sought in this science.
25. Metaphysics of The Healing, VIII.1.1 [327].
26. Metaphysics of The Healing, VIII.1.2 [327] (Marmura trans., modified).
27. Metaphysics of The Healing, VIII.8.5 [342] (Marmura trans., modified).
28. God is the first efficient cause because of the connection Avicenna makes between
the “the necessary” and “existence.” Earlier he had established that “the necessary” means
“the assuredness of existence” (Metaphysics of The Healing, I.5.20 [36]), and that necessary
existence in itself must be one, uncaused, peerless, and simple (ibid., I. 6–7, esp. I.7.13–14
[47]). Avicenna does not deny that God is a final cause; on the contrary, he clearly holds the
good is desired as an end, and that God is the most pure good (ibid., VIII.6.2–4 [355–356]).
Nevertheless, in the Metaphysics of the Healing, Avicenna does not attempt to demonstrate the
existence of God on the basis of final causality. See Robert Wisnovsky, “Final and Efficient
Causality in Avicenna’s Cosmology and Theology,” Quaestio 2 (2002): 97–123.
29. Davidson, Houser, and Bertolacci all provide healthy antidotes to such mistaken
interpretations of Avicenna’s Metaphysics of the Healing, I.6–7. See supra n16, and my forth-
coming, “Where Does Avicenna Demonstrate the Existence of God?”
30. Metaphysics of the Healing VIII.1.8–9 [329].
156 Philosophy in the Abrahamic Traditions

31. See Jules A. Baisnée, “St. Thomas Aquinas’s Proofs of the Existence of God Presented
in their Chronological Order,” in Philosophical Studies in Honor of the Very Reverend Ignatius
Smith, 0. P., ed. John K. Ryan (Westminster, MD: Newman Press, 1952): 29–64.
32. In de Trinitate, V.4. All quotations from this work will be taken from Thomas
Aquinas, The Division and Methods of the Sciences, Questions V–VI of the Commentary on
Boethius’ De Trinitate, trans. Armand Maurer, 4th ed., (Toronto: PIMS, 1986).
33. In de Trinitate, V.4 (Maurer trans.). See In I Sent., Prol., q. 1, a. 2; q. 1, a. 3, qc. 1;
In de Trinitate, V.1, ad 9; De veritate, 14.9; SCG I. 3–4; II.4; ST I.1.1, ad 3; I.1.7.
34. See ST I.1.1; I.1.7; DV 14.9, ad 3.
35. Compare St. Thomas’s presentation of the subject, principles, ends of metaphysics,
and the names of metaphysics (e.g., first philosophy and divine science) in the proemium to
his commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics with Avicenna’s Metaphysics of the Healing, I.1.9–10
[1]; I.2.18 [11]; I.3.12–16 [21–23]. See Stephen F. Brown, “Avicenna and the Unity of the
Concept of Being,” Franciscan Studies 25 (1965): 117–150; Timothy B. Noone, “St. Albert
on the Subject of Metaphysics and Demonstrating the Existence of God” Medieval Philosophy
and Theology 2 (1992): 31–52; Bertolacci, “Avicenna and Averroes on The Proofs of God’s
Existence and The Subject Matter of Metaphysics.” For additional secondary literature on
this topic, see supra n3.
36. Interpretations of the five ways should distinguish between the argument’s point
of departure (e.g., the evidence that needs to be explained), its modus operandi (e.g., the
kind(s) of causal series at work in the proof ), its proximate trajectory (e.g., the conclusion
that there is some first cause), and its many remote trajectories (e.g., the way a particular
proof and its conclusion will be employed in St. Thomas’s account of divine simplicity, divine
perfection and God’s creative act). The point of departure of the first way is from natural
philosophy, yet it immediately turns to defend the premise “everything moved is moved
by another” by way of the properly metaphysical division between act and potency (see In
de Trinitate, V.1, ad 6; In meta., Proem; In XII meta., lt. 4, n. 2482). This is a particularly
significant detail if we compare it to the first way from SCG. In SCG I.13, Aquinas presents
three arguments to defend the same premise; the first two arguments are clearly drawn from
natural philosophy, but the third draws upon Physics 8.5, 257a39 and the division between
act and potency. This provides the argument with a more universal field of application
that allows it to extend beyond the cosmological horizon of natural philosophy; with act
and potency in hand the premises now can apply to immaterial beings and conclude with
a being that must be a separate first mover that is an absolutely unmoved pure actuality, in
contrast to a mere first mover of the cosmos—a distinction Aquinas addresses at the end
of the second way from motion found in SCG I.13 (see David Twetten, “Clearing a ‘Way’
for Aquinas: How the Proof from Motion Concludes to God,” Proceedings of the American
Catholic Philosophical Association 70 (1996): 259–278, esp. 269–271). But the arguments
from motion in SCG I.13 are important for another reason as well. As Gilson points out
(Thomism, 79), unlike the other ways, St. Thomas does not actually mention the kind of
causality involved in the first way; yet, in SCG Aquinas explicitly asserts the importance of
Metaphysics XII’s use of final causality for showing that the first mover is immobile and pure
act. Taken together, these points further substantiate the contention that the first way is not
an argument taken from natural philosophy simpliciter. For others who, at least, agree with
this last point, see Owens, “The Conclusion of the Prima Via”; Dewan, “St. Thomas’s Fourth
Way and Creation,” 376n17; Twetten, “Clearing a ‘Way’ for Aquinas,” 267–271; Wippel,
Metaphysical Thought, 420–421, n59; 444–459 (esp. 456–457); Rudi TeVelde, Aquinas on
Why the Five Ways? 157

God: The “Divine Science” of the Summa Theologiae (Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2006), 48–60;
Thomas J. White, Wisdom in the Face of Modernity: A Study in Thomistic Natural Theology
(Sapientia Press, 2009), 205–216, 234–245.
37. Gilson, Thomism, 80. Many have questioned whether the five ways, taken individu-
ally or collectively, demonstrate the existence of God, and if they do, some wonder whether
they demonstrate the existence of one and the same God. These problems are far too com-
plicated to address adequately here. Many of these concerns have been deftly handled in
David Twetten, “To Which ‘God’ Must a Proof of God’s Existence Conclude for Aquinas?”
in Laudemus Viros Gloriosos: Essays in Honor of Armand Maurer, CSB, ed. R. E. Houser (Notre
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2007), 146–183.
38. The inquiries into ens mobile and the four causes begin in natural philosophy, but
are transposed into a metaphysical horizon, either by the ontological consideration of ens
commune as divided into act and potency, or by an aitiological consideration of the first and
ultimate causes, respectively. The ultimate destination of all these investigations is ens divi-
num (see In I sent., Prol. 4), which is the apogee of metaphysical theology and the subject of
sacred theology. Even the subject of mathematics finds its causal foundation in God as the
first principle of all beings (see ST I.44.1, ad 3).
39. See ST I.1.3, ad 2.
40. ST I.44.4, ad 4 (my translation).
41. We should not overlook the significance of the connection between the four causes
in the five ways and their relation to Aquinas’s treatment of creation in q. 44, which is set
up in terms of the four causes, as well as the similar doctrines we find in De potentia 3.5;
In de causis I; In II meta., lt. 2–4; In V meta., lt. 2–3. Note also the order from efficient to
material, formal, and final causes in the last four of the five ways and ST I.44.1–4. Why
does it not follow the proper order of the causes from material to formal, efficient, and final
causes? I submit, it is because St. Thomas is following Avicenna’s order from Metaphysics of
the Healing, VIII.1–3.
42. See Avicenna, Metaphysics of the Healing, VIII.6. For a more detailed demonstration
of this last point, along with a comparison of the doctrines found in St. Thomas’s earlier
works, see the article by R. E. Houser in this volume as well as R. E. Houser, “Aristotle and
Two Medieval Aristotelians on the Nature of God,” International Philosophical Quarterly 51.3
(2011): 355–375.
43. See also ST I.44.1; 3–4.
44. See DV 3.3; SCG I.26; In II meta., lt. 4, n. 320–329; In V meta., lt. 2, n. 764; ST
I.14.6; 15.1–3; In Johannis, Prol. It is surprising that Dewan overlooks the fact that “formality,”
when taken in terms of exemplar causality, includes all perfections of being, including good-
ness and existence (see Dewan, Five Ways, 10n39). Consequently, his dismissal of the fourth
way’s use of “formal” causality was premature (see ST I.6.4; Wippel, Metaphysical Thought,
469–479; esp. 472–474). For a clarification of this aspect of divine exemplar causality, see
Mark Jordan, “The Intelligibility of the World and the Divine Ideas in Aquinas,” Review of
Metaphysics 38 (1984): 17–32 (esp. 21–23).
45. See De potentia 3.5; ST I.44.2.
46. See SCG I.17; ST I.3.8.
47. “Accordingly a possibility of non-being is in the nature of those things alone whose
matter is subject to contrariety of forms: whereas it belongs to other things by their nature to
158 Philosophy in the Abrahamic Traditions

exist of necessity, all possibility of nonexistence being removed from their nature.” Thomas
Aquinas, On the Power of God (Quaestiones disputatae de potentia dei), trans. English Dominican
Fathers (Newman Press, 1932), q. 5, a. 3. St. Thomas distinguishes two senses of possible:
(1) absolute and (2) by power or potentiality. The latter is divided into possible by (2a) active
potentiality and (2b) passive potentiality. This quote from De potentia is locating the possibility
for nonexistence within the nature of material things because they have prime matter, which is
the first passive potentiality (see ST I.44.2, ad 2), and this is the meaning of possible existent
identified in the opening of the third way. These divisions are essential for understanding the
differences between Avicenna and Aquinas on possibility. Like Avicenna, Aquinas holds that
the common nature of any creature, as considered in itself, is existentially neutral; however,
unlike Avicenna, St. Thomas holds that the existential neutrality of a created nature does not
entail that it has a potentiality or possibility for nonexistence. For Aquinas, some creatures
are essentially necessary—though none are existentially necessary—and other creatures are
essentially possible. The former are immaterial creatures, whereas the latter are material and
are called “possible existents” in the third way. See DV 5.2, ad 6; ST I. 25.3; 46.1 obj. 1 and
ad 1; 50.5, ad 3; 75.6; De potentia 5.3, ad 2; In I de caelo, lt. 25; lt. 29, nn. 284–285; In VII
meta., lt. 6, n. 1388. For studies on the meaning of “possibility” in St. Thomas, see Joseph
Owens, “‘Cause of Necessity’ in Aquinas’ Tertia Via,” Mediaeval Studies 33 (1971): 21–45;
Lawrence Dewan, “St. Thomas and the Possibles,” The New Scholasticism 53 (1979): 76–85;
John F. Wippel, “The Reality of Nonexisting Possibles according to Thomas Aquinas, Henry
of Ghent, and Godfrey of Fontaines,” Review of Metaphysics 34 (1981): 729–758.
48. Allow me to summarize briefly how this study’s interpretation is similar to and dif-
ferent from others. Unlike Elders and others, I agree with Gilson, Owens, and Wippel that
it is completely unreasonable to maintain that Aquinas thought that the five ways were the
only ways to demonstrate God’s existence. I also agree with Wippel and others that there
are five distinct arguments in the five ways. Like Kenny, I think that the point of departure
of the third way is from material causality. Unlike Elders and Kenny, I do not attempt to
reduce the five ways to the four causes, but have identified the point of departure of four
of the five ways with the effects of the four causes. Not only does the first way not mention
causality, it clearly is more concerned with act, potency, and motion. Hence, I agree with
Wippel that, “As for the former suggestion, that the five ways can be reduced to some single
logical scheme, some have attempted to reduce all five of them in some way to the four
causes. Such attempts strike me as forced. First of all, there is the obvious point that there
are five ways but only four supreme kinds of causes.” (Wippel, Metaphysical Thought, 498).
My view also dodges Wippel’s other objections to using the four causes to interpret the five
ways and introduces a connection between the five ways and Avicenna’s demonstrations,
which is not addressed by Wippel. Many Thomists have raised reasonable doubts about
some attempts to find a unifying principle in the five ways (see Owens, “Aquinas and the
Five Ways,” 141; Wippel, Metaphysical Thought, 500); I hope that this study has provided a
reasonable alternative interpretation of their unity.
I would like to acknowledge my debt and gratitude to my dissertation director,
R. E. Houser, for allowing me to read his unpublished paper “Avicenna and the Five Ways,”
which was the inspiration for this study. I would also like to thank Brian Carl and Therese
Scarpelli Cory for carefully reading through this paper and offering me numerous suggestions,
objections, and criticisms, as well as to credit Brandon Dahm, Benjamin Smith, Domenic
D’Ettore, Joshua Hochschild, and Jon McGinnis for many helpful comments.

You might also like